im钱包软件下载|ethical concerns

作者: im钱包软件下载
2024-03-13 04:52:22

This service is not available.

::CLOUDFLARE_ERROR_1000S_BOX::

Ethical Considerations in Research | Types & Examples

Ethical Considerations in Research | Types & Examples

FAQ

About us

Our editors

Apply as editor

Team

Jobs

Contact

My account

Orders

Upload

Account details

Logout

My account

Overview

Availability

Information package

Account details

Logout

Admin

Log in

Search

Proofreading & Editing

Thesis

Paper

AI Proofreader

Essay Checker

PhD dissertation

APA editing

Academic editing

College admissions essay

Personal statement

English proofreading

Spanish, French, or German

About our services

Proofreading services

Proofreading & editing example

Essay coaching example

Happiness guarantee

Plagiarism Checker

Citation Tools

Citation Generator

Check your Citations

Cite with Chrome

AI Writing

AI Proofreader

Paraphrasing Tool

Grammar Checker

Summarizer

AI Detector

Knowledge Base

Proofreading & Editing

Plagiarism Checker

Citation Tools

AI Writing

Knowledge Base

FAQ

About us

My account

My account

Admin

Log in

Nederlands

English

Deutsch

Français

Italiano

Español

Svenska

Dansk

Suomi

Norwegian Bokmål

Back

Thesis

Paper

AI Proofreader

Essay Checker

PhD dissertation

APA editing

Academic editing

College admissions essay

Personal statement

English proofreading

Spanish, French, or German

About our services

Proofreading services

Proofreading & editing example

Essay coaching example

Happiness guarantee

Back

Citation Generator

Check your Citations

Cite with Chrome

Back

AI Proofreader

Paraphrasing Tool

Grammar Checker

Summarizer

AI Detector

Back

Our editors

Apply as editor

Team

Jobs

Contact

Back

Orders

Upload

Account details

Logout

Back

Overview

Availability

Information package

Account details

Logout

Have a language expert improve your writing

Proofreading Services

Run a free plagiarism check in 10 minutes

Plagiarism Checker

Generate accurate citations for free

Citation Generator

Home

Knowledge Base

Methodology

Ethical Considerations in Research | Types & Examples

MethodologyAn introduction to research methodsResearch approachesInductive vs. deductiveInductive vs. deductiveInductive reasoningDeductive reasoningQualitative vs. quantitativeQualitative vs. quantitativeQuantitative researchQualitative researchMixed methods researchPrimary researchSecondary researchAction researchTypes of research comparedResearch designsResearch design step by stepDescriptiveCorrelationalExperimentalQuasi-experimentalCross-sectionalLongitudinalCase studyEthnographicExploratoryExplanatoryVariables and hypothesesTypes of variablesIndependent vs. dependentExplanatory vs. responseMediator vs. moderatorExtraneous variablesConfounding variablesControl variablesCorrelation vs. causationOperationalizationWriting hypothesesReliability & validityReliability vs. validityTypes of reliabilityTypes of validityTypes of validityInternal vs. externalInternal validityEcological validityExternal validityConstruct validityContent validityCriterion validityConcurrent validityDiscriminant validityFace validityConvergent validityPredictive validityReproducibility & replicabilityRandom & systematic errorTriangulationSamplingPopulation vs. sampleInclusion and exclusion criteriaSampling methodsProbability vs. non-probability samplingProbability samplingNon-probability samplingSimple random samplingSystematic samplingStratified samplingCluster samplingQuota samplingPurposive samplingConvenience samplingMultistage samplingSnowball samplingCollecting dataStep-by-stepSurveysDoing survey researchDesigning questionnairesLikert scalesDouble-barreled questionInterviewsTypes of interviews in researchStructured interviewSemi-structured interviewUnstructured interviewFocus groupExperimentsDesigning an experimentControlled experimentsControl groupsRandom assignmentBlindingBetween-subjects designWithin-subjects designObservational studiesStep-by-stepNaturalistic observationCase–control studyCohort studyRetrospective cohort studyProspective cohort studyParticipant observationQualitative observationQuantitative observationSystematic reviewPreparing dataData cleansingTranscribing interviewsAnalyzing dataStatistical analysisContent analysisDiscourse analysisThematic analysisTextual analysisWriting up methodsMethodology in a thesisMethods in APA styleResearch ethicsPeer review

Interesting topics

AMA style

Working with sources

IEEE

Commonly confused words

Commas

Definitions

UK vs. US English

Research bias

Nouns and pronouns

College essay

Parts of speech

Sentence structure

Verbs

Common mistakes

Effective communication

Using AI tools

Fallacies

Rhetoric

APA Style 6th edition

Applying to graduate school

Statistics

Chicago Style

Language rules

Methodology

MLA Style

Research paper

Academic writing

Starting the research process

Dissertation

Essay

Tips

APA Style 7th edition

APA citation examples

Citing sources

Plagiarism

Try our other services

Proofreading & Editing

Have a human editor polish your writing to ensure your arguments are judged on merit, not grammar errors.

Get expert writing help

AI Proofreader

Get unlimited proofreading for 30 days

Try for free

Plagiarism Checker

Compare your paper to billions of pages and articles with Scribbr’s Turnitin-powered plagiarism checker.

Run a free check

Citation Generator

Generate accurate APA, MLA, and Chicago citations for free with Scribbr's Citation Generator.

Start citing

Paraphraser

Rewrite and paraphrase texts instantly with our AI-powered paraphrasing tool.

Try for free

Grammar Checker

Eliminate grammar errors and improve your writing with our free AI-powered grammar checker.

Try for free

Ethical Considerations in Research | Types & Examples

Published on

October 18, 2021

by

Pritha Bhandari.

Revised on

June 22, 2023.

Ethical considerations in research are a set of principles that guide your research designs and practices. Scientists and researchers must always adhere to a certain code of conduct when collecting data from people.

The goals of human research often include understanding real-life phenomena, studying effective treatments, investigating behaviors, and improving lives in other ways. What you decide to research and how you conduct that research involve key ethical considerations.

These considerations work to

protect the rights of research participants

enhance research validity

maintain scientific or academic integrity

This article mainly focuses on research ethics in human research, but ethical considerations are also important in animal research.Table of contentsWhy do research ethics matter?Getting ethical approval for your studyTypes of ethical issuesVoluntary participationInformed consentAnonymityConfidentialityPotential for harmResults communicationExamples of ethical failuresOther interesting articlesFrequently asked questions about research ethics

Why do research ethics matter?

Research ethics matter for scientific integrity, human rights and dignity, and collaboration between science and society. These principles make sure that participation in studies is voluntary, informed, and safe for research subjects.

You’ll balance pursuing important research objectives with using ethical research methods and procedures. It’s always necessary to prevent permanent or excessive harm to participants, whether inadvertent or not.

Defying research ethics will also lower the credibility of your research because it’s hard for others to trust your data if your methods are morally questionable.

Even if a research idea is valuable to society, it doesn’t justify violating the human rights or dignity of your study participants.

Here's why students love Scribbr's proofreading services

Trustpilot

Discover proofreading & editing

Getting ethical approval for your study

Before you start any study involving data collection with people, you’ll submit your research proposal to an institutional review board (IRB).

An IRB is a committee that checks whether your research aims and research design are ethically acceptable and follow your institution’s code of conduct. They check that your research materials and procedures are up to code.

If successful, you’ll receive IRB approval, and you can begin collecting data according to the approved procedures. If you want to make any changes to your procedures or materials, you’ll need to submit a modification application to the IRB for approval.

If unsuccessful, you may be asked to re-submit with modifications or your research proposal may receive a rejection. To get IRB approval, it’s important to explicitly note how you’ll tackle each of the ethical issues that may arise in your study.

Types of ethical issues

There are several ethical issues you should always pay attention to in your research design, and these issues can overlap with each other.

You’ll usually outline ways you’ll deal with each issue in your research proposal if you plan to collect data from participants.

Ethical issue

Definition

Voluntary participation

Your participants are free to opt in or out of the study at any point in time.

Informed consent

Participants know the purpose, benefits, risks, and funding behind the study before they agree or decline to join.

Anonymity

You don’t know the identities of the participants. Personally identifiable data is not collected.

Confidentiality

You know who the participants are but you keep that information hidden from everyone else. You anonymize personally identifiable data so that it can’t be linked to other data by anyone else.

Potential for harm

Physical, social, psychological and all other types of harm are kept to an absolute minimum.

Results communication

You ensure your work is free of plagiarism or research misconduct, and you accurately represent your results.

Voluntary participation

Voluntary participation means that all research subjects are free to choose to participate without any pressure or coercion.

All participants are able to withdraw from, or leave, the study at any point without feeling an obligation to continue. Your participants don’t need to provide a reason for leaving the study.

It’s important to make it clear to participants that there are no negative consequences or repercussions to their refusal to participate. After all, they’re taking the time to help you in the research process, so you should respect their decisions without trying to change their minds.

Example of voluntary participationWhen recruiting participants for an experiment, you inform all potential participants that they are free to choose whether they want to participate, and they can withdraw from the study anytime without any negative repercussions.

Voluntary participation is an ethical principle protected by international law and many scientific codes of conduct.

Take special care to ensure there’s no pressure on participants when you’re working with vulnerable groups of people who may find it hard to stop the study even when they want to.

Prevent plagiarism. Run a free check.

Try for free

Informed consent

Informed consent refers to a situation in which all potential participants receive and understand all the information they need to decide whether they want to participate. This includes information about the study’s benefits, risks, funding, and institutional approval.

Example of informed consentYou recruit participants outside a train station for a quick survey.

You make sure to provide all potential participants with all the relevant information about

what the study is about

the risks and benefits of taking part

how long the study will take

your supervisor’s contact information and the institution’s approval number

You also let them know that their data will be kept confidential, and they are free to stop filling in the survey at any point for any reason. They can also withdraw their information by contacting you or your supervisor.

Usually, you’ll provide participants with a text for them to read and ask them if they have any questions. If they agree to participate, they can sign or initial the consent form. Note that this may not be sufficient for informed consent when you work with particularly vulnerable groups of people.

If you’re collecting data from people with low literacy, make sure to verbally explain the consent form to them before they agree to participate.

For participants with very limited English proficiency, you should always translate the study materials or work with an interpreter so they have all the information in their first language.

In research with children, you’ll often need informed permission for their participation from their parents or guardians. Although children cannot give informed consent, it’s best to also ask for their assent (agreement) to participate, depending on their age and maturity level.

Anonymity

Anonymity means that you don’t know who the participants are and you can’t link any individual participant to their data.

You can only guarantee anonymity by not collecting any personally identifying information—for example, names, phone numbers, email addresses, IP addresses, physical characteristics, photos, and videos.

In many cases, it may be impossible to truly anonymize data collection. For example, data collected in person or by phone cannot be considered fully anonymous because some personal identifiers (demographic information or phone numbers) are impossible to hide.

You’ll also need to collect some identifying information if you give your participants the option to withdraw their data at a later stage.

Data pseudonymization is an alternative method where you replace identifying information about participants with pseudonymous, or fake, identifiers. The data can still be linked to participants but it’s harder to do so because you separate personal information from the study data.

Example of data pseudonymizationYou’re conducting a survey with college students. You ask participants to enter demographic information including their age, gender identity, nationality, and ethnicity. With all this information, it may be possible for other people to identify individual participants, so you pseudonymize the data.

Each participant is given a random three-digit number. You separate their personally identifying information from their survey data and include the participant numbers in both files. The survey data can only be linked to personally identifying data via the participant numbers.

Confidentiality

Confidentiality means that you know who the participants are, but you remove all identifying information from your report.

All participants have a right to privacy, so you should protect their personal data for as long as you store or use it. Even when you can’t collect data anonymously, you should secure confidentiality whenever you can.

Example of confidentialityTo keep your data confidential, you take steps to safeguard it and prevent any threats to data privacy. You store all signed consent forms in a locked file drawer, and you password-protect all files with survey data.

Only other researchers approved by the IRB are allowed to access the study data, and you make sure that everyone knows and follows your institution’s data privacy protocols.

Some research designs aren’t conducive to confidentiality, but it’s important to make all attempts and inform participants of the risks involved.

Example of focus group confidentialityIn a focus group study, you invite five people to give their opinions on a new student service in a group setting.

Before beginning the study, you ask everyone to agree to keep what’s discussed confidential and to respect each other’s privacy. You also note that you cannot completely guarantee confidentiality or anonymity so that participants are aware of the risks involved.

Potential for harm

As a researcher, you have to consider all possible sources of harm to participants. Harm can come in many different forms.

Psychological harm: Sensitive questions or tasks may trigger negative emotions such as shame or anxiety.

Social harm: Participation can involve social risks, public embarrassment, or stigma.

Physical harm: Pain or injury can result from the study procedures.

Legal harm: Reporting sensitive data could lead to legal risks or a breach of privacy.

It’s best to consider every possible source of harm in your study as well as concrete ways to mitigate them. Involve your supervisor to discuss steps for harm reduction.

Make sure to disclose all possible risks of harm to participants before the study to get informed consent. If there is a risk of harm, prepare to provide participants with resources or counseling or medical services if needed.

Example of potential for harmIn a study on stress, you survey college students on their alcohol consumption habits.

Some of these questions may bring up negative emotions, so you inform participants about the sensitive nature of the survey and assure them that their responses will be confidential.

You also provide participants with information about student counseling services and information about managing alcohol use after the survey is complete.

Results communication

The way you communicate your research results can sometimes involve ethical issues. Good science communication is honest, reliable, and credible. It’s best to make your results as transparent as possible.

Take steps to actively avoid plagiarism and research misconduct wherever possible.

Plagiarism

Plagiarism means submitting others’ works as your own. Although it can be unintentional, copying someone else’s work without proper credit amounts to stealing. It’s an ethical problem in research communication because you may benefit by harming other researchers.

Self-plagiarism is when you republish or re-submit parts of your own papers or reports without properly citing your original work.

This is problematic because you may benefit from presenting your ideas as new and original even though they’ve already been published elsewhere in the past. You may also be infringing on your previous publisher’s copyright, violating an ethical code, or wasting time and resources by doing so.

In extreme cases of self-plagiarism, entire datasets or papers are sometimes duplicated. These are major ethical violations because they can skew research findings if taken as original data.

Example of duplicationYou’re conducting a meta-analysis on whether working from home is related to better stress management. You gather all studies on this topic that meet your search criteria.

You notice that two published studies have similar characteristics even though they are from different years. Their sample sizes, locations, treatments, and results are highly similar, and the studies share one author in common.

If you enter both data sets in your analyses, you get a different conclusion compared to when you only use one data set. Including both data sets would distort your overall findings.

Research misconduct

Research misconduct means making up or falsifying data, manipulating data analyses, or misrepresenting results in research reports. It’s a form of academic fraud.

These actions are committed intentionally and can have serious consequences; research misconduct is not a simple mistake or a point of disagreement about data analyses.

Research misconduct is a serious ethical issue because it can undermine academic integrity and institutional credibility. It leads to a waste of funding and resources that could have been used for alternative research.

Example of misconduct (MMR vaccine misinformation)In 1998, Andrew Wakefield and others published a now-debunked paper claiming that the measles, mumps, and rubella (MMR) vaccine causes autism in children.

Later investigations revealed that they fabricated and manipulated their data to show a nonexistent link between vaccines and autism. Wakefield also neglected to disclose important conflicts of interest, and his medical license was taken away.

This fraudulent work sparked vaccine hesitancy among parents and caregivers. The rate of MMR vaccinations in children fell sharply, and measles outbreaks became more common due to a lack of herd immunity.

In reality, there is no risk of children developing autism from the MMR or other vaccines, as shown by many large studies. Although the paper was retracted, it has actually received thousands of citations.

Examples of ethical failures

Content warningThis section contains discussion of violence, racism, and ableism.

Research scandals with ethical failures are littered throughout history, but some took place not that long ago.

Some scientists in positions of power have historically mistreated or even abused research participants to investigate research problems at any cost. These participants were prisoners, under their care, or otherwise trusted them to treat them with dignity.

To demonstrate the importance of research ethics, we’ll briefly review two research studies that violated human rights in modern history.

Nazi experimentsNazi doctors and researchers performed painful and horrific experiments on thousands of imprisoned people in concentration camps from 1942 to 1945.

These experiments were inhumane and resulted in trauma, permanent disabilities, or death in many cases.

The participation of prisoners was always forced, as consent was never sought. Participants often belonged to marginalized communities, including Jewish people, disabled people, and Roma people.

After some Nazi doctors were put on trial for their crimes, the Nuremberg Code of research ethics for human experimentation was developed in 1947 to establish a new standard for human experimentation in medical research.

Tuskegee syphilis studyThe Tuskegee syphilis study was an American public health study that violated research ethics throughout its 40-year run from 1932 to 1972. In this study, 600 young black men were deceived into participating with a promise of free healthcare that was never fulfilled.

In reality, the actual goal was to study the effects of the disease when left untreated, and the researchers never informed participants about their diagnoses or the research aims.

Although participants experienced severe health problems, including blindness and other complications, the researchers only pretended to provide medical care.

When treatment became possible in 1943, 11 years after the study began, none of the participants were offered it, despite their health conditions and high risk of death.

By the end of the study, 128 participants had died of syphilis or related complications. The study ended only once its existence was made public and it was judged to be “medically unjustified.”

Ethical failures like these resulted in severe harm to participants, wasted resources, and lower trust in science and scientists. This is why all research institutions have strict ethical guidelines for performing research.

Other interesting articles

If you want to know more about statistics, methodology, or research bias, make sure to check out some of our other articles with explanations and examples.

Statistics

t table

Normal distribution

Measures of central tendency

Chi square tests

Confidence interval

Quartiles & Quantiles

Methodology

Cluster sampling

Stratified sampling

Thematic analysis

Cohort study

Peer review

Ethnography

Research bias

Implicit bias

Cognitive bias

Conformity bias

Hawthorne effect

Availability heuristic

Attrition bias

Social desirability bias

Frequently asked questions about research ethics

What are ethical considerations in research?

Ethical considerations in research are a set of principles that guide your research designs and practices. These principles include voluntary participation, informed consent, anonymity, confidentiality, potential for harm, and results communication.

Scientists and researchers must always adhere to a certain code of conduct when collecting data from others.

These considerations protect the rights of research participants, enhance research validity, and maintain scientific integrity.

Why do research ethics matter?

Research ethics matter for scientific integrity, human rights and dignity, and collaboration between science and society. These principles make sure that participation in studies is voluntary, informed, and safe.

What’s the difference between anonymity and confidentiality?

Anonymity means you don’t know who the participants are, while confidentiality means you know who they are but remove identifying information from your research report. Both are important ethical considerations.

You can only guarantee anonymity by not collecting any personally identifying information—for example, names, phone numbers, email addresses, IP addresses, physical characteristics, photos, or videos.

You can keep data confidential by using aggregate information in your research report, so that you only refer to groups of participants rather than individuals.

What is research misconduct?

Research misconduct means making up or falsifying data, manipulating data analyses, or misrepresenting results in research reports. It’s a form of academic fraud.

These actions are committed intentionally and can have serious consequences; research misconduct is not a simple mistake or a point of disagreement but a serious ethical failure.

Cite this Scribbr article

If you want to cite this source, you can copy and paste the citation or click the “Cite this Scribbr article” button to automatically add the citation to our free Citation Generator.

Bhandari, P.

(2023, June 22). Ethical Considerations in Research | Types & Examples. Scribbr.

Retrieved March 12, 2024,

from https://www.scribbr.com/methodology/research-ethics/

Cite this article

Is this article helpful?

1487

94

You have already voted. Thanks :-)

Your vote is saved :-)

Processing your vote...

Pritha Bhandari

Pritha has an academic background in English, psychology and cognitive neuroscience. As an interdisciplinary researcher, she enjoys writing articles explaining tricky research concepts for students and academics.

Other students also liked

Data Collection | Definition, Methods & Examples

Data collection is the systematic process of gathering observations or measurements in research. It can be qualitative or quantitative.

1722

What Is Self-Plagiarism? | Definition & How to Avoid It

Self-plagiarism means reusing work that you have already submitted for a class or published.

45

How to Avoid Plagiarism | Tips on Citing Sources

Avoid plagiarism by keeping track of the sources you use, quoting or paraphrasing them properly, and citing them correctly.

717

Scribbr

Our editors

Jobs

Partners

FAQ

Copyright, Community Guidelines, DSA & other Legal Resources

Our services

Plagiarism Checker

Proofreading Services

Citation Generator

AI Proofreader

AI Detector

Paraphrasing Tool

Grammar Checker

Free Text Summarizer

Citation Checker

Knowledge Base

Contact

info@scribbr.com

+1 (510) 822-8066

4.6

Nederlands

English

Deutsch

Français

Italiano

Español

Svenska

Dansk

Suomi

Norwegian Bokmål

Terms of Use

Privacy Policy

Happiness guarantee

Search...

×

0 results

What is your plagiarism score?

Scribbr Plagiarism Checker

101 Ethical Issues Examples (2024)

101 Ethical Issues Examples (2024)

Skip to content

Main Menu

Home

Essay Plan Templates

Choose a SubjectMenu Toggle

Sociology

Psychology

Education Studies

TeamMenu Toggle

About The Helpful Professor

Peer Review and Editorial Process

Meet the Team

Contact

Our YouTube Channel

Search for:

Search

101 Ethical Issues ExamplesBy

Chris Drew (PhD)

/ August 28, 2023 /

Leave a Comment

An ethical issue is a situation, either personal or social, that requires the application of a moral or ethical framework to form a judgment or choose a course of action (Ferrell et al., 2018; Barrett, 2018).

Ethical issues are often presented as dilemmas (Ferrell et al., 2018). In such situations, the issue is not clear-cut. This may be because there is a balance of positives and negatives, trade-off between your options (such as in opportunity costs), or contrasting moral frameworks that each have their own internal validity.

Some contemporary issues that may be considered to have an ethical component are presented below.

Contents

show

Ethical Issues Examples

Conclusion

References

Ethical Issues Examples

1. Animal Rights: Humans have greatly benefited from eating animals. However, through factory farming of animals, a conundrum has emerged about how much responsibility we have to animals that are used for human food. Dilemmas we may face may include deciding on whether to buy free-range eggs, how to ethically source our meat, or whether to become vegetarian – more on that below!

2. Vegetarianism/Veganism: Building on the above, some people choose not to consume animal products due to moral, health, or environmental concerns. Some philosophers, such as Peter Singer, argue that animals should have rights similar to humans and shouldn’t be harmed for food, clothing, or experimentation.

3. Fast Fashion: Buying inexpensive clothes can save us money, but it can have social ramifications. Often, fast fashion clothing is produced by people under poor working conditions (i.e. they’re underpaid) and can cause environmental costs because the clothing ends up in landfill very quickly.

4. Climate Change: While the evidence that humans are contributing to climate change is almost irrefutable, we still face a dilemma about what steps should be taken to combat it – solutions like carbon taxes, for example, may end up harming people short-term.

5. Genetic Engineering: Altering the genes of organisms raises concerns about unforeseen consequences and playing “God”. But it could also help us to eradicate evil diseases such as cancers and dramatically reduce child mortality.

6. Privacy in the Digital Age: Personal data, such as our location and search history, is used by companies to create targeted advertisements. Some think this is fine (we get relevant ads, for example), while others think it’s a violation of privacy that could be exploited.

7. Artificial Intelligence & Ethics: The potential misuse of AI, potential widespread job loss, and its power to cause harm in the hands of the wrong people, is a hot issue since the rise of GPT large language models.

8. Organ Transplants: Deciding who gets priority for organ donations is a tricky issue that could, if we’re not careful, make us prioritize some people over others – which in itself could be a violation of human rights.

9. Food Waste: One third of all food produced is thrown away each year. The ethics surrounding throwing away edible food in light of global hunger is a hot topic worthy of greater discussion.

10. Child Labor: The use of children for labor, often in harsh conditions, primarily in poorer countries, continues to this day. Sometimes, things we own have been produced by children far down the supply lune.

11. Euthanasia: This refers to allowing terminally ill patients to end their lives. Some people rely on religious frameworks to argue against this (such as my mother – a staunch Catholic), while others consider it a compassionate option so long as the person chooses that option with sound mind.

12. Deforestation: The removal of trees to build infrastructure is necessary, but it can also harm the climate and biodiversity. Finding an appropriate balance is a key ethical issue.

13. Water Usage: Some areas of the world are water rich, while others are water poor. Finding ways to ethically allocate freshwater is a matter of ethics. This is especially true when people upstream take the good water at the expense of people downstream (such as in the Murray-Darling Basin in Australia.

14. Single-Use Plastics: The environmental impact of items used briefly and discarded is enormous. Finding a way to address this is of importance to help reduce all our ecological footprints.

15. Cultural Appropriation: The borrowing or imitation of elements from another culture without respect or understanding can be harmful. The issue lies in whether it’s a form of appreciation or disrespectful theft, potentially perpetuating damaging stereotypes.

15. Overfishing: Fishing is a means of livelihood for many, yet, unsustainable practices are depleting fish populations at an alarming rate. The ethical challenge lies in finding a balance between livelihoods, consumer demand, and ecological sustainability.

16. Internet Censorship: Censorship can protect individuals from harmful content, but it also risks infringing upon freedom of speech and information. The question becomes who should control this and how far it should go.

17. Surveillance: While surveillance can enhance security and crime prevention, it raises concerns about privacy and misuse of data. Establishing limits and safeguards is vital, but the decision of who should set these rules is a major ethical contemplation.

18. Fair Trade: This movement advocates for better trading conditions and rights for producers in developing countries. However, the ethics of fair trade are complex, such as deciding fair prices and whether the system actually benefits the intended communities.

19. Stem Cell Research: This field holds the potential for major medical advancements but raises ethical issues due to the source of some stem cells—human embryos, posing questions about the value and sanctity of human life.

20. Child Privacy Online: Protecting personal data of children online is paramount but raises questions about who is responsible – parents, software companies, or government entities.

21. GMO Foods: Genetically Modified Organisms may solve food security issues, but they raise ethical concerns about biodiversity, as well as the ‘naturalness’ of food, and unforeseen public health issues.

22. Sports Doping: The use of performance-enhancing substances in sports poses ethical dilemmas about fairness, health effects, and the nature of competition itself. The tension lies where ambition counters fair play.

23. Advertising to Children: Children are impressionable, and advertising can manipulate their desires and behaviours. The ethical issue is whether and how businesses should be regulated in their marketing towards children.

24. Cyberbullying: This form of bullying can have severe psychological impacts. The ethical challenge lies in developing effective regulations to prevent it, whilst upholding freedoms of speech and expression.

25. Consumer Data Mining: The mining of consumer data can result in more personalized experiences but raises concerns about privacy, consent, and security. It sparks debates on who should control data and how it can be used.

26. Factory Farming: This method, emphasizing high-volume, low-cost meat production, generates ethical concerns about animal welfare, environmental impacts, and workers’ conditions.

27. Endangered Species: Protecting endangered species sometimes clashes with human development and livelihoods. The ethical concern lies in balancing conservation with societal advancement.

28. Land Rights: Disputes over land embody a range of ethical issues, including indigenous rights, historical injustices, and sustainable use; deciding who has a rightful claim can be a complex decision.

29. Digital Piracy: The unauthorized distribution of copyrighted material infringes intellectual property rights but is regularly justified as a rebellion against perceived corporate greed. The ethical discussion revolves around fairness, respect, and how entertainment should be valued.

30. Responsible Tourism: Traveling can stimulate economies and foster understanding, but it can also be harmful, both to the environment and local cultures. The ethical challenge is to promote responsible tourism that respects local customs and values ecological preservation.

31. Biased Algorithms: As AI becomes more integral in our lives, the issue of algorithms inadvertently perpetuating human biases arises. Addressing this requires broad collaborations to eliminate discriminatory results.

32. Renewable vs. Non-Renewable Energy: While renewable energy is better for the environment, transitioning from non-renewable sources could disrupt economies and livelihoods. Striking a balance is an ethical priority.

33. Planned Obsolescence: This business strategy involves deliberately designing products to become obsolete after a certain period. Ethics come into play when considering long term environmental impact and consumer rights.

34. Sweatshops: The operation of sweatshops involves human rights abuses but can provide jobs where few exist. The ethical concerns involve workers’ rights, consumer responsibility, and the role of global trade practice.

35. Censorship in Media: While done to protect people from harmful or sensitive content, it can lead to public misinformation and ignorance. The ethical debate revolves around security, free speech, and the power dynamics between governments and citizens.

36. Gene Editing for Enhancement: Altering human genes to get rid of harmful health conditions is one thing, but using it to enhance our physical or cognitive abilities is another. It raises questions about the line between ‘natural’ and ‘unnatural’, the potential widening of social inequalities and even what it means to be human.

37. Fair Taxation: The issue of taxation forms a key ethical dilemma: we need money to pay for public services, but excessive taxation can disincentivize work, business, and investment.

38. Body Image in Media: The ideal body image portrayed by the media can lead to unhealthy comparisons & behaviors, including eating disorders and body dysmorphia. This issue questions the responsibility media has in promoting a diverse and realistic range of body types versus its right to market aspirational content.

39. Child Soldiers: In some conflict zones, children are forced into fighting as soldiers. This practice not only robs them of their childhood but also exposes them to extreme physical and psychological harm.

40. Human Trafficking: Regrettably, human trafficking, a form of modern slavery, continues to occur on a global scale. The act of trading humans for forced labor or sexual exploitation poses serious ethical issues, not to mention gross human rights violations.

41. Digital Divide: The gap between those who have access to the internet and digital devices and those who do not is known as the digital divide. With growing reliance on digital technologies, addressing this gap is crucial to ensure equal opportunities for education, work, and communication (Reynolds, 2014).

42. Autonomous Vehicles: The use of AI in driving raises several ethical questions, from the algorithms used in decision-making during accidents to the security of these vehicles against hacking. Furthermore, job displacement due to automation is a significant concern.

43. Invasive Species: There’s a dilemma between controlling invasive species, which often involves methods that can harm them and the impact they have on native species and ecosystems. These decisions often weigh the preservation of biodiversity against animal welfare.

44. Girls’ Education: The education of girls in developing nations continues to be an issue of great important, with girls often afforded dramatically fewer rights than boys. This doesn’t only cause gender inequality – it also stifles nations’ economies.

45. Vaccination: While vaccines can protect society from deadly diseases, many also argue that they may infringe on an individual’s freedom of choice. Many people who choose not to be vaccinated are often convinced by nefarious actors and fake news perpetrators – such as, sadly, prominent politicians – who falsely claim links between vaccines and conditions such as autism.

46. Littering: Littering has a significant impact on the environment, wildlife, and our living spaces. The ethical considerations revolve around our individual and collective responsibilities to keep our planet clean.

47. Whistleblowing: Those who expose institutional malpractices or corruption often face risks, including job loss and physical danger. The ethical dilemmas involve finding a balance between ensuring the truth is heard and protecting the individual whistleblower’s rights.

48. Public vs. Private Education: Balancing the offered pros of private education—such as smaller classes and specialized programs—with the commitment to ensure high-quality public education for all students is a key ethical issue.

49. Preservation of Historical Sites: The clash between preserving architectural heritage and the demand for new, modern infrastructure poses an ethical problem. It brings into question the value we place on culture and history versus development and progress.

50. Child Marriage: Prevalent in certain cultures and societies, child marriage raises concerns about the violation of children’s rights, their physiological and psychological well-being, and the perpetuation of poverty and gender inequality.

51. Economic Inequality: The gap between the wealthy and the poor, both within countries and worldwide, poses ethical questions about fairness, social justice, and the roles and responsibilities of individuals, corporations, and governments.

52. Freedom of Speech vs. Hate Speech: While freedom of speech is a fundamental democratic right, it can sometimes intersect with promoting hate speech. Striking a balance between protecting individuals’ rights to express their views and preventing harm towards marginalized groups presents an ongoing ethical dilemma.

53. Animal Testing: Used in medical research and cosmetics testing, this practice raises ethical considerations of animal welfare, rights, and the justification of causing harm for potential human benefit.

54. Right to Internet Access: As the internet becomes more integral to daily life, the idea it should be a basic human right is suggested. But this opens up ethical discussions about access, affordability, and who should ensure these conditions are met.

55. Artificially Increasing Food Prices: This practice can make food inaccessible to poorer populations, leading to ethical questions about fairness, exploitation, and basic human rights to food and nourishment.

56. Zoos and Aquariums: While providing an educational opportunity for the public, and often acting as conservation centers, the business of keeping animals in captivity for entertainment faces moral questions. Balancing the welfare and quality of life for these animals against their conservation and our learning needs can be controversial.

57. Cultural Relativism: The premise that no culture’s ethics are superior to another means that potentially harmful practices such as female genital mutilation or child labor may be condoned in some societies. Deciding where to draw the line between respecting cultural differences and global human rights efforts can be challenging.

58. Right to be Forgotten: In our digital age, past mistakes can follow us forever. The ethical issue here is finding a balance between someone’s right to wipe their online slate clean, and the public’s right to information, particularly information which protects them.

59. Human Cloning: While the science is still premature, human cloning could potentially offer benefits such as organ transplants. However, concerns over the potential misuse of technology, the rights of clones, and unforeseen consequences present major ethical dilemmas.

60. Space Exploration vs. Earth Issues: It’s inspiring to reach for the stars, but allocating extensive resources to space exploration whilst Earth faces urgent crises such as poverty and climate change creates a significant moral debate.

61. Landfills: They keep our homes clean, but the environmental impact of dumping waste into land, including risks to local water supplies and wildlife, is of ethical concern. It forces us to evaluate our consumer habits and waste-management systems.

62. Colonialism’s Legacy: Divergent perspectives on whether to address past harms through restitution or reparation, or to focus on development on an individual country basis, and understandings of history, present significant ethical dilemmas.

63. Microtransactions in Gaming: Consumers, particularly young people, can spend substantial money on digital goods in games. Fairness and the potential exploitation of vulnerable consumers are pressing ethical concerns here.

64. Unpaid Internships: They may provide experience and a foot-in-the-door, but they can also favor those who can afford to work without pay, reinforcing socio-economic inequalities. Ethical dilemmas include combating this potential elitism and the exploitation of young workers.

65. Influencer Transparency: As influencers become major product pushers, issues such as undisclosed sponsorships and the manipulation of trust become critical ethical considerations.

66. Population Control: With increasing global population comes strain on resources and environmental systems. However, discussion of any form of population control often strikes chords of draconian tactics and human rights violations.

67. Redistribution of Wealth: Balancing economic inequality through wealth redistribution speaks to principles of fairness and social justice, but it also raises concerns about individual rights, especially those of the wealthy.

68. Monopolies: They can innovate and bring efficiencies, but they can also abuse their power, causing harm to consumers and potential competitors. Policies to regulate or dismantle them raise ethical considerations around business and consumer rights.

69. Preservation of Indigenous Languages: When a language dies, a way of understanding the world dies with it. Principles of cultural respect, diversity, and prevention of linguistic discrimination are central to this ethical issue.

70. Public Health vs. Personal Freedom: Measures such as mandatory vaccination infringe on individual liberties but protect public health. Striking a balance between community well-being and personal rights sparks complex ethical debates.

71. Habitat Destruction: Building for human needs often destroys local ecosystems. Ethical considerations include species rights, human wants, and ecological and climate impacts.

72. Media Bias: Media outlets have significant influence over public opinion, yet they are often accused of bias. Ethics here include a commitment to reporting truthfully and equitably, protecting democratic processes (Plaisance, 2017).

73. Ethical Consumption: It’s often difficult to make fully informed, ethical consumption choices. From product origin transparency issues to the potential costs of ethical goods, this issue raises questions about personal responsibilities, global inequalities, and market transparency.

74. Parental Rights vs. Child’s Best Interest: Balancing a parent’s rights to raise their children as they see fit creates challenging ethical questions, especially if the parents choose to hide important information from their children or raise them in an unsafe environment.

75. Work-Life Balance: Ensuring fair pay, humane working hours, and sufficient vacation while maintaining business’ profitability and productivity is at play here.

76. Right to Repair: The ethical dilemma is between a consumer’s right to repair their own purchased goods and a company’s right to control intellectual property, affecting affordability, sustainability, and consumer rights.

77. Religious Freedom: Freedom of religion is guaranteed in most democratic countries. However, ethical issues continue to arise around religion, such as whether religious institutions should pay taxes and separation of church and state.

78. Fake News: Dissemination of false information can mislead the public and shake trust in democratic institutions. Balancing free speech with informational integrity and societal repercussions ensues as a major ethical dilemma.

79. Captive Breeding: While captive breeding programs can help save endangered species from extinction, they raise ethical questions. Are we justified in limiting an animal’s freedom for the sake of their survival? How can we ensure adequate living conditions for captive-bred animals?

80. Public Surveillance: Public security aims to protect us, but what about our right to privacy? Striking a balance between guaranteeing public safety and upholding individual privacy, especially with technological advances in surveillance, paves the way to ongoing debates.

81. Circus Animals: While traditional circuses may provide entertainment, they confine animals to unnatural living conditions and often subject them to harsh training methods. Is our entertainment worth the potential suffering of animals?

82. Duty to Report: There can be moral dilemmas surrounding our duty to report illegal activities. Should we breach friendships, family ties or professional confidence to uphold the rule of law?

83. Economic Sanctions: Designed as a non-violent method to enforce international norms, economic sanctions can inadvertently harm innocent citizens, raising questions about their ethical value.

84. Native Advertising: Native ads, which blend with editorial content, can be deceptive and blur the line between entertainment and salesmanship. This raises ethical questions surrounding transparency and the consumer’s right to know.

85. Digital Detox: As technology permeates every aspect of our lives, the idea of consciously disconnecting feels increasingly rebellious. This raises ethical questions about the extent of our reliance on digital media and the length these companies go to retain our attention.

86. Preservation vs. Progress: Balancing the preservation of historical sites or natural environments against infrastructural and technological progress can provoke ethical and moral debates about respecting our past and catering to our future.

87. Ethical Banking: As some financial institutions are implicated in questionable practices such as supporting fossil fuels or oppressive regimes, the rise of ethical banking poses questions about financial responsibility and the role of money in supporting societal wellbeing or harm.

88. Welfare Programs: The allocation of welfare raises ethical questions. Who should be eligible, and how much support should they receive? Is it okay to let some people struggle if that means more money goes to the most vulnerable?

89. Healthcare: Some places in the world consider healthcare to be a right for all citizens, implementing universal access to all through progressive taxation. But many nations in the world do not guarantee this, causing it to become an area of ethical contention.

90. Access to Education: Disparities in the quality of, and access to, education fuels social inequality, raising ethical questions about fair and equitable opportunities for all children.

91. Captive Marine Life: The capture and captivity of marine life for entertainment, research or conservation purposes face ethical scrutiny, most particularly concerning animal welfare, ethics of captivity and conservation issues.

92. Child Stardom: Forcing or allowing children into the limelight at a young age can potentially rob them of a normal childhood and expose them prematurely to high-pressure situations. Balancing parental ambitions, child protections and artistic potential is a challenging ethical questions.

93. Cognitive Enhancements: The use of drugs or procedures to augment cognitive abilities presents ethical dilemmas. Do these advantages deepen societal inequalities? Is it ethical to pathologize normal cognitive variations?

94. Food Labeling: Ethical issues arise when companies use misleading, false, or confusing language on food labels, which may compromise the consumer’s right to know what they’re consuming, especially in regard to health and environmental implications.

95. Charity Efficiency: While donating to charity is a noble cause, not all charities use donations efficiently. The ethical issue here is how much transparency there should be about how donations are used, and how efficiency should be measured.

96. Right to Clean Water: Despite being a basic human necessity, access to clean water isn’t universally granted. Ensuring equal access poses an ethical challenge, particularly when determining responsibility between citizens, corporations, and governments.

97. End-of-Life Care: Decisions around end-of-life care, such as palliative care and withholding treatment, raise profound ethical concerns about the value and quality of life, autonomy and dignity, and the role of medical professionals in these decisions.

98. Use of Drones: The use of drones raises ethical concerns, particularly around privacy – are we okay with potentially being watched without our consent? There are also issues of public safety and questions about the legality of their proliferation.

99. Upcycling vs. Recycling: Both are better for the environment than simply throwing things away, but which is better? Upcycling can create new, usable items, but it can use more resources than simply recycling the material.

100. Digital Accessibility: As our world becomes more digitized, it’s crucial to ensure everyone, including those with disabilities, can equitably access information and services. Failing to design for all users raises ethical implications about inclusivity and diversity in the digital era.

101. Isolationism: There is extensive debate over whether nations should participate in global institutions like the UN and attempt to support victimized nations like Ukraine and Taiwan, or whether to retreat from global politics.

Conclusion

Ethical issues are all around us, presenting conflicting courses of action that often diverge based upon differing worldviews and conflicting ideologies. Sometimes, our ethical issues are also simply based upon a trade-off between two good but different options, or two bad options (in which case you need to consider the lesser evil).

References

Ferrell, O. C., Fraedrich, J., & Ferrell, L. (2018). Business ethics: Ethical decision making & cases (12th ed.). Boston: Cengage.

Barrett, C. (2018). Everyday ethics for practicing planners. London: Routledge.

Plaisance, P-L. (2017). Media Ethics: Key Principles for Responsible Practice (2nd ed.). Sage Publications.

Reynolds, G. (2014). Ethics in Information Technology (4th ed.). New York: Cengage Learning.

Chris Drew (PhD)

Website

|

+ posts

Dr. Chris Drew is the founder of the Helpful Professor. He holds a PhD in education and has published over 20 articles in scholarly journals. He is the former editor of the Journal of Learning Development in Higher Education. [Image Descriptor: Photo of Chris]

Chris Drew (PhD)

https://helpfulprofessor.com/author/chris-drew-phd/

50 Durable Goods Examples

Chris Drew (PhD)

https://helpfulprofessor.com/author/chris-drew-phd/

100 Consumer Goods Examples

Chris Drew (PhD)

https://helpfulprofessor.com/author/chris-drew-phd/

30 Globalization Pros and Cons

Chris Drew (PhD)

https://helpfulprofessor.com/author/chris-drew-phd/

17 Adversity Examples (And How to Overcome Them)

Leave a Comment Cancel ReplyYour email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *Type here..Name*

Email*

Website

This Article was Last Expert Reviewed on August 28, 2023 by Chris Drew, PhD

We cite peer reviewed academic articles wherever possible and reference our sources at the end of our articles. All articles are edited by a PhD level academic. Learn more about our academic and editorial standards.Cite this Article in your Essay (APA Style)Drew, C. (August 20, 2023). 101 Ethical Issues Examples. Helpful Professor. https://helpfulprofessor.com/ethical-issues-examples/Search for a Study GuideSearchReady to Write your Essay? I'll Help you get Started:

My 5 Paragraph Intro Method

How to Start your Essay

How to Paraphrase Like a Pro

My 5 C's Conclusions Method

How to Edit your Essay for 13% Higher Grades

How to Overcome Study Procrastination

Privacy PolicyTerms and ConditionsDisclaimerAccessibility Statement

As an Amazon Associate I earn from qualifying purchases.

About The Helpful Professor®

Copyright © 2024 Helpful ProfessorHelpful Professor® is a USPTO Registered TrademarkAll the advice on this site is general in nature. Seekprofessional input on your specific circumstances. Studentsshould always cross-check any information on this site with their course teacher.

Ethics | Definition, History, Examples, Types, Philosophy, & Facts | Britannica

Ethics | Definition, History, Examples, Types, Philosophy, & Facts | Britannica

Search Britannica

Click here to search

Search Britannica

Click here to search

Login

Subscribe

Subscribe

Home

Games & Quizzes

History & Society

Science & Tech

Biographies

Animals & Nature

Geography & Travel

Arts & Culture

Money

Videos

On This Day

One Good Fact

Dictionary

New Articles

History & Society

Lifestyles & Social Issues

Philosophy & Religion

Politics, Law & Government

World History

Science & Tech

Health & Medicine

Science

Technology

Biographies

Browse Biographies

Animals & Nature

Birds, Reptiles & Other Vertebrates

Bugs, Mollusks & Other Invertebrates

Environment

Fossils & Geologic Time

Mammals

Plants

Geography & Travel

Geography & Travel

Arts & Culture

Entertainment & Pop Culture

Literature

Sports & Recreation

Visual Arts

Companions

Demystified

Image Galleries

Infographics

Lists

Podcasts

Spotlights

Summaries

The Forum

Top Questions

#WTFact

100 Women

Britannica Kids

Saving Earth

Space Next 50

Student Center

Home

Games & Quizzes

History & Society

Science & Tech

Biographies

Animals & Nature

Geography & Travel

Arts & Culture

Money

Videos

ethics

Table of Contents

ethics

Table of Contents

Introduction & Top QuestionsThe origins of ethicsMythical accountsIntroduction of moral codesProblems of divine originPrehuman ethicsNonhuman behaviourKinship and reciprocityAnthropology and ethicsThe history of Western ethicsAncient civilizations to the end of the 19th centuryThe ancient Middle East and AsiaThe Middle EastIndiaChinaAncient and Classical GreeceAncient GreeceSocratesPlatoAristotleLater Greek and Roman ethicsThe StoicsThe EpicureansChristian ethics from the New Testament to the ScholasticsEthics in the New TestamentSt. AugustineSt. Thomas Aquinas and the ScholasticsThe Renaissance and the ReformationMachiavelliThe first ProtestantsThe British tradition from Hobbes to the utilitariansHobbesEarly intuitionists: Cudworth, More, and ClarkeShaftesbury and the moral sense schoolButler on self-interest and conscienceThe climax of moral sense theory: Hutcheson and HumeThe intuitionist response: Price and ReidUtilitarianismPaleyBenthamMillSidgwickThe Continental tradition from Spinoza to NietzscheSpinozaLeibnizRousseauKantHegelMarxNietzscheWestern ethics from the beginning of the 20th centuryMetaethicsMoore and the naturalistic fallacyModern intuitionismEmotivismExistentialismUniversal prescriptivismLater developments in metaethicsMoral realismKantian constructivism: a middle ground?Irrealist views: projectivism and expressivismEthics and reasons for actionNormative ethicsThe debate over consequentialismVarieties of consequentialismObjections to consequentialismAn ethics of prima facie dutiesRawls’s theory of justiceRights theoriesNatural law ethicsVirtue ethicsFeminist ethicsEthical egoismApplied ethicsEqualityAnimalsEnvironmental ethicsWar and peaceAbortion, euthanasia, and the value of human lifeBioethics

References & Edit History

Quick Facts & Related Topics

Images

For Students

ethics summary

Related Questions

What is ethics?

How is ethics different from morality?

Why does ethics matter?

Is ethics a social science?

What did Aristotle do?

Read Next

What’s the Difference Between Morality and Ethics?

Philosophers to Know, Part I

Plato and Aristotle: How Do They Differ?

What’s the Difference Between Morality and Ethics?

Order in the Court: 10 “Trials of the Century”

Discover

Celebrating Ramadan

12 Greek Gods and Goddesses

7 Puzzling Plane Disappearances

Why Doesn’t Arizona Observe Daylight Saving Time?

Have Any U.S. Presidents Decided Not to Run For a Second Term?

Nostradamus and His Prophecies

7 Deadliest Weapons in History

Home

Philosophy & Religion

Ethical Issues

History & Society

ethics

philosophy

Actions

Cite

verifiedCite

While every effort has been made to follow citation style rules, there may be some discrepancies.

Please refer to the appropriate style manual or other sources if you have any questions.

Select Citation Style

MLA

APA

Chicago Manual of Style

Copy Citation

Share

Share

Share to social media

Facebook

Twitter

URL

https://www.britannica.com/topic/ethics-philosophy

Give Feedback

External Websites

Feedback

Corrections? Updates? Omissions? Let us know if you have suggestions to improve this article (requires login).

Feedback Type

Select a type (Required)

Factual Correction

Spelling/Grammar Correction

Link Correction

Additional Information

Other

Your Feedback

Submit Feedback

Thank you for your feedback

Our editors will review what you’ve submitted and determine whether to revise the article.

External Websites

Business LibreTexts - What is Ethics?

Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy - Ethics and Contrastivism

Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy - Empathy and Sympathy in Ethics

VIVA Open Publishing - Ethics and Society - Ethical Behavior and Moral Values in Everyday Life

Philosophy Basics - Ethics

American Medical Association - Journal of Ethics - Triage and Ethics

Psychology Today - Ethics and Morality

Government of Canada - Treasury Board of Canada Secretariat - What is ethics?

Cornell Law School - Legal Information Institute - Ethics

Britannica Websites

Articles from Britannica Encyclopedias for elementary and high school students.

ethics and morality - Student Encyclopedia (Ages 11 and up)

Print

print

Print

Please select which sections you would like to print:

Table Of Contents

Cite

verifiedCite

While every effort has been made to follow citation style rules, there may be some discrepancies.

Please refer to the appropriate style manual or other sources if you have any questions.

Select Citation Style

MLA

APA

Chicago Manual of Style

Copy Citation

Share

Share

Share to social media

Facebook

Twitter

URL

https://www.britannica.com/topic/ethics-philosophy

Feedback

External Websites

Feedback

Corrections? Updates? Omissions? Let us know if you have suggestions to improve this article (requires login).

Feedback Type

Select a type (Required)

Factual Correction

Spelling/Grammar Correction

Link Correction

Additional Information

Other

Your Feedback

Submit Feedback

Thank you for your feedback

Our editors will review what you’ve submitted and determine whether to revise the article.

External Websites

Business LibreTexts - What is Ethics?

Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy - Ethics and Contrastivism

Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy - Empathy and Sympathy in Ethics

VIVA Open Publishing - Ethics and Society - Ethical Behavior and Moral Values in Everyday Life

Philosophy Basics - Ethics

American Medical Association - Journal of Ethics - Triage and Ethics

Psychology Today - Ethics and Morality

Government of Canada - Treasury Board of Canada Secretariat - What is ethics?

Cornell Law School - Legal Information Institute - Ethics

Britannica Websites

Articles from Britannica Encyclopedias for elementary and high school students.

ethics and morality - Student Encyclopedia (Ages 11 and up)

Also known as: moral philosophy

Written by

Peter Singer

Peter Singer is the Ira W. DeCamp Professor of Bioethics at the University Center for Human Values, Princeton University. A specialist in applied ethics, he approaches ethical issues from a secular, preference-utilitarian...

Peter Singer

Fact-checked by

The Editors of Encyclopaedia Britannica

Encyclopaedia Britannica's editors oversee subject areas in which they have extensive knowledge, whether from years of experience gained by working on that content or via study for an advanced degree. They write new content and verify and edit content received from contributors.

The Editors of Encyclopaedia Britannica

Last Updated:

Feb 14, 2024

Article History

Table of Contents

Code of Hammurabi

See all media

Category:

History & Society

Also called:

moral philosophy

(Show more)

Key People:

Socrates

Aristotle

Plato

St. Augustine

Immanuel Kant

(Show more)

Related Topics:

history of ethics

Trolley problem

legal ethics

biocentrism

optimism

(Show more)

On the Web:

VIVA Open Publishing - Ethics and Society - Ethical Behavior and Moral Values in Everyday Life (Feb. 14, 2024)

(Show more)

See all related content →

Top Questions

What is ethics?The term ethics may refer to the philosophical study of the concepts of moral right and wrong and moral good and bad, to any philosophical theory of what is morally right and wrong or morally good and bad, and to any system or code of moral rules, principles, or values. The last may be associated with particular religions, cultures, professions, or virtually any other group that is at least partly characterized by its moral outlook.How is ethics different from morality?Traditionally, ethics referred to the philosophical study of morality, the latter being a more or less systematic set of beliefs, usually held in common by a group, about how people should live. Ethics also referred to particular philosophical theories of morality. Later the term was applied to particular (and narrower) moral codes or value systems. Ethics and morality are now used almost interchangeably in many contexts, but the name of the philosophical study remains ethics.Why does ethics matter?Ethics matters because (1) it is part of how many groups define themselves and thus part of the identity of their individual members, (2) other-regarding values in most ethical systems both reflect and foster close human relationships and mutual respect and trust, and (3) it could be “rational” for a self-interested person to be moral, because his or her self-interest is arguably best served in the long run by reciprocating the moral behaviour of others.Is ethics a social science?No. Understood as equivalent to morality, ethics could be studied as a social-psychological or historical phenomenon, but in that case it would be an object of social-scientific study, not a social science in itself. Understood as the philosophical study of moral concepts, ethics is a branch of philosophy, not of social science.ethics, the discipline concerned with what is morally good and bad and morally right and wrong. The term is also applied to any system or theory of moral values or principles.(Read Britannica’s biography of this author, Peter Singer.)How should we live? Shall we aim at happiness or at knowledge, virtue, or the creation of beautiful objects? If we choose happiness, will it be our own or the happiness of all? And what of the more particular questions that face us: is it right to be dishonest in a good cause? Can we justify living in opulence while elsewhere in the world people are starving? Is going to war justified in cases where it is likely that innocent people will be killed? Is it wrong to clone a human being or to destroy human embryos in medical research? What are our obligations, if any, to the generations of humans who will come after us and to the nonhuman animals with whom we share the planet?Ethics deals with such questions at all levels. Its subject consists of the fundamental issues of practical decision making, and its major concerns include the nature of ultimate value and the standards by which human actions can be judged right or wrong.The terms ethics and morality are closely related. It is now common to refer to ethical judgments or to ethical principles where it once would have been more accurate to speak of moral judgments or moral principles. These applications are an extension of the meaning of ethics. In earlier usage, the term referred not to morality itself but to the field of study, or branch of inquiry, that has morality as its subject matter. In this sense, ethics is equivalent to moral philosophy.Although ethics has always been viewed as a branch of philosophy, its all-embracing practical nature links it with many other areas of study, including anthropology, biology, economics, history, politics, sociology, and theology. Yet, ethics remains distinct from such disciplines because it is not a matter of factual knowledge in the way that the sciences and other branches of inquiry are. Rather, it has to do with determining the nature of normative theories and applying these sets of principles to practical moral problems.

Get a Britannica Premium subscription and gain access to exclusive content.

Subscribe Now

This article, then, will deal with ethics as a field of philosophy, especially as it has developed in the West. For coverage of religious conceptions of ethics and the ethical systems associated with world religions, see Buddhism; Christianity; Confucianism; Hinduism; Jainism; Judaism; Sikhism. The origins of ethics Mythical accounts Introduction of moral codes When did ethics begin and how did it originate? If one has in mind ethics proper—i.e., the systematic study of what is morally right and wrong—it is clear that ethics could have come into existence only when human beings started to reflect on the best way to live. This reflective stage emerged long after human societies had developed some kind of morality, usually in the form of customary standards of right and wrong conduct. The process of reflection tended to arise from such customs, even if in the end it may have found them wanting. Accordingly, ethics began with the introduction of the first moral codes. Virtually every human society has some form of myth to explain the origin of morality. In the Louvre in Paris there is a black Babylonian column with a relief showing the sun god Shamash presenting the code of laws to Hammurabi (died c. 1750 bce), known as the Code of Hammurabi. The Hebrew Bible (Old Testament) account of God’s giving the Ten Commandments to Moses (flourished 14th–13th century bce) on Mount Sinai might be considered another example. In the dialogue Protagoras by Plato (428/427–348/347 bce), there is an avowedly mythical account of how Zeus took pity on the hapless humans, who were physically no match for the other beasts. To make up for these deficiencies, Zeus gave humans a moral sense and the capacity for law and justice, so that they could live in larger communities and cooperate with one another. That morality should be invested with all the mystery and power of divine origin is not surprising. Nothing else could provide such strong reasons for accepting the moral law. By attributing a divine origin to morality, the priesthood became its interpreter and guardian and thereby secured for itself a power that it would not readily relinquish. This link between morality and religion has been so firmly forged that it is still sometimes asserted that there can be no morality without religion. According to this view, ethics is not an independent field of study but rather a branch of theology (see moral theology).

There is some difficulty, already known to Plato, with the view that morality was created by a divine power. In his dialogue Euthyphro, Plato considered the suggestion that it is divine approval that makes an action good. Plato pointed out that, if this were the case, one could not say that the gods approve of such actions because they are good. Why then do they approve of them? Is their approval entirely arbitrary? Plato considered this impossible and so held that there must be some standards of right or wrong that are independent of the likes and dislikes of the gods. Modern philosophers have generally accepted Plato’s argument, because the alternative implies that if, for example, the gods had happened to approve of torturing children and to disapprove of helping one’s neighbours, then torture would have been good and neighbourliness bad.

General ethical concerns – The Reflect! platform

General ethical concerns – The Reflect! platform

Skip to content

The Reflect! platform

Main Menu

About Us

Materials

Wicked problems

General ethical concerns

Publications

Videos

The Argument Assessment Tutor (AAT)

DeCoPP

Template to upload teams and users

How to

How to search for and share research articles

How to formulate a problem?

How to develop a stakeholder analysis

How to listen

How to develop a symphysis proposal

How to construct an argument

Glossary

For Instructors

Learning goals

Things to keep in mind

Guidance for work on the symphysis proposal

Workshops

Communication

Terms of Service

Search

Search for:

Search

General ethical concerns

Ethics or morality is about what one should or should not do. The great classical meta-ethical theories—deontology, utilitarianism, virtue ethics—and other meta-ethical approaches provide different strategies to justify what we should or should not do. These are general justification strategies that can be applied to argue for (or against) any concrete decision or for general ethical principles that prescribe how one should act. However, we can think about ethics not only as a question of justification but also as a question about which kind of behavior people find concerning. Such an empirical or descriptive approach to ethics is realized in this document.

Every ethical concern can be translated into an ethical principle that provides instructions about what we should or should not do to address this concern. For example, if we are concerned about hate speech, we might consider the establishment of a series of ethical principles: do not engage in hate speech; intervene when you observe hate speech; support the creation of social structures, institutions, or laws that allow the prosecution of hate speech; and so on. Since there can be an infinite number of ethical concerns and corresponding principles, an empirical approach to ethical principles will never be able to provide a complete list of ethical concerns or principles. And since the things people find concerning might change over time, might vary in different cultures, or might be controversial within societies, different people will find different sets of concerns and principles important.

It is possible, however, to develop typologies of ethical or moral concerns. In cultural psychology, Shweder, Much, Mahapatra, & Park (1997) distinguished three clusters of moral themes in a large body of interviews: autonomy, community and divinity. Based on this, Jonathan Haidt and colleagues developed a distinction of six “universal cognitive modules upon which cultures construct moral matrices” (Haidt 2012, p. 124):

Care / harm

Fairness / cheating

Loyalty / betrayal

Authority / subversion

Sanctity / degradation

Liberty / oppression

I would suggest a different typology. It starts from a distinction of negative and positive ethical concerns—what should not be done and what should be done—and those that have both a positive and negative dimension. Under each of the three is then a distinction of very general concerns provided, each with more specific concerns. References are either to the literature or to students who provided additional ideas.

As negative ethical concerns are listed: harm; limiting autonomy and liberty; and changing identities and living conditions.

For positive concerns: Improving things; creating fair and just living conditions; worrying about cleanliness or purity; and moral concerns that are driven by certain loyalties.

Both positive and negative concerns include: What is required based on an intrinsic value of things; based on the sanctity of things; and what is required by accepted authority.

1.       Negative ethical concerns: What should not be done

1.1       Harm

Annihilating humanity

Genocide

Crime against humanity (Sands 2016; http://www.nytimes.com/2016/05/29/books/review/east-west-street-by-philippe-sands.html)

War or violent conflict

“Being able to live to the end of a human life of normal length” (Nussbaum 1999, pp. 41-42)

Bodily health. “Being able to have good health, including reproductive health” (ibid.)

Bodily integrity. “Being able to move freely from place to place, being able to be secure against violent assault, including sexual assault” (ibid.), against harm, pain, and suffering.

Excluding people from the community they want to be a part of.

Undermining someone’s dignity, social standing, reputation, or honor, or their cultural, religious, social, sexual, or ideological identity and self-perception. As Jeremy Waldron (2012) writes: “A person’s dignity … is their social standing, the fundamentals of basic reputation that entitle them to be treated as equals in the ordinary operations of society. Their dignity is something they can rely on—in the best case implicitly and without fuss, as they live their lives, go about their business, and raise their families” (p. 5)

Stealing of property, including data

Structural violence. Johan Galtung (1969) originally coined this term to refer to any constraint on human potential due to economic, social, cultural, religious, or political structures. Lacking access to resources, to political power, to education, to health care, or to legal standing, are forms of structural violence. When inner city children have inadequate schools, when gays and lesbians are fired for their sexual orientation, when institutions and customs treat men and women differently, when transgender and non-binary people adequate medical care is denied or they experience a “higher than average likelihood of being murdered” (Chris Thayer), when laborers toil in inhumane conditions, when people of color endure environmental toxins in their neighborhoods, when certain groups of people were able to accumulate wealth, individual, societal, or political power much later in history then others (voting rights or the ability to purchase mortgages) so that they are at a generational disadvantage (Alexandra Erwin), then structural violence exists. Unfortunately, even those who are victims of structural violence often do not see the systematic ways in which their plight might be choreographed by unequal and unfair distribution of society’s resources. Can be applied to individuals, races, classes, groups, and nations (e.g., global economic injustice).

Imposing tacit biases on people by the social order or by institutions such as the media so that the awareness of structural violence is prevented and violent social structures reinforced (Paul Demerritt, 2017)

Losing the “assurance that there will be no need to face hostility, violence, discrimination, or exclusion.” This is the way Waldron (2012, p. 4) describes the harm done by hate speech. However, having a sense that there is a risk of harm, a sense of insecurity or missing protection and safety can also be caused by direct threats or by gestures and other signs.

Having a sense that you cannot be yourself, that there is no space “to test your actions, and potentially fail or make mistakes” (Rainey Jernigan, 2017)

Offending people, i.e. causing them to feel threatened in their dignity, reputation, honor,

Undermining trust (e.g. by breaking a promise, cheating, or violating rights; this is harm to social relations)

1.2       Limiting autonomy and liberty

Slavery

Coercion

Limiting people’s freedom of making informed decisions

Manipulating people so that they make decisions against their own interests (Christopher Cook, 2017)

Diminishing people’s responsibility or accountability (e.g., in paternalism)

Limiting access to information and knowledge, including transparency of decision making

Overburdening control by governments or governance structures

Making private information accessible to others (privacy)

1.3       Change of identities and living conditions

Changing what it means to be human or to live in human societies, for example by certain technological innovations or substantial societal changes (Bauman 2004; Economist 2016; Ford 2015; Frey & Osborne 2013; Kaplan 2015; Peck 2010; Rifkin 1995; Susskind & Susskind 2015)

Changing living conditions (e.g. by excessive taxation)

Diminishing diversity of life styles (e.g., totalitarianism)

2.       Positive ethical concerns: What should be done

2.1       Improving things

Helping others in need

Supporting others, caring for others

Developing one’s own talents

Developing certain attitudes or character traits such as generosity

Developing general happiness, quality of life, self-confidence, , pride in one’s achievements, and conviviality, acknowledgement of one’s way of life

Actively preventing harm or reducing harmful realities (see 1.1)

Promoting social relations or a sense of community

Promoting virtues (truthfulness, trust, prudence, bravery, altruism, politeness, etc.)

Advancement of knowledge

Development of new or better technologies

Inclusion of everybody in decision or policy making, especially of those whose voice, needs, interests, or values have traditionally been marginalized. Whereas related ideas have been discussed above under “structural violence” in the section on “harm,” they should also be discussed under the mission of “improving things.” “Historically, societies have privileged select few members of society, who have disproportionately held positions of power socially, politically, and economically. To this day, such power dynamics are still in existence and are readily discernable along the lines of race, ethnicity, culture, gender, socio-economic status, religion, ability, etc…  I argue that an ethical responsibility lies in promoting and furthering inclusion as to increase the voices among the aforementioned groups such that they achieve adequate representation among the public and political spheres of society” (Darian Agnew, 2017)

2.2       Creating fair and just living conditions

Equals should be treated equally (Schick & Vaughn 2013, p. 338)

“Just” and “fair” are properties of social relations, or of activities that promote social relations, or of people who perform those activities. Social relations are just and fair if and only if they realize a system of rights and obligations that both protects the weak and arbitrarily disadvantaged and guarantees that everybody gets what he or she deserves in the distribution of social and economic goods and in the adjudication of socially imposed burdens on individuals such as taxation and punishment. Attempts to determine what someone deserves focus on principles that are justified based on either (a) the assumption that they are universally true and binding; (b) their usefulness for the sustainability of social relations; (c) an agreement—hypothetical or real—among the people who constitute these social relations; or (d) on any combination of the other possibilities. (My own definition)

Injustice: unequal distribution of benefits and burdens (e.g. discrimination; Tuskegee syphilis experiments)

2.3       Worrying about cleanliness or purity of

one’s own body and thoughts

community (e.g., social order)

natural environment

actions with regard to a divine entity

2.4       Moral concerns that are driven by certain loyalties and respect to

family

in-group (community, social class, race, nation, etc.)

ideas or traditions

leaders or representatives of groups

divine entities

3.       Both positive and negative ethical concerns

3.1       What is required based on an intrinsic value of things

Respect for things as valuable in themselves

3.2       What is required based on a sanctity of things

Reverence for sacred places, times, events, rituals, actions, persons, entities, etc.

3.3       What is required by accepted authority

Parents

Tradition, culture

Religious authoritative texts (e.g. the Bible; Quran)

Accepted leaders

References

Bauman, Z. (2004). Wasted lives: modernity and its outcasts. Cambridge: Polity.

Economist. (2016). Artificial intelligence: The return of the machinery question. Economist, 11; Special Report 11-16. Retrieved from http://www.economist.com/news/special-report/21700761-after-many-false-starts-artificial-intelligence-has-taken-will-it-cause-mass

Ford, M. (2015). Rise of the robots : technology and the threat of a jobless future. New York: Basic Books, a member of the Perseus Books Group.

Frey, C. B., & Osborne, M. A. (2013). The Future of Employment: How susceptible are jobs to computerization? Retrieved from http://www.oxfordmartin.ox.ac.uk/downloads/academic/The_Future_of_Employment.pdf

Galtung, J. (1969). Violence, Peace, and Peace Research. [Article]. Journal of Peace Research(3), 167-191.

Haidt, J. (2012). The righteous mind: Why good people are divided by politics and religion (1st ed.). New York: Pantheon Books.

Kaplan, J. (2015). Humans need not apply : a guide to wealth and work in the age of artifcial intelligence. New Haven: Yale University Press.

Nussbaum, M. C. (1999). Sex & social justice. New York: Oxford University Press.

Peck, D. (2010). How a New Jobless Era Will Transform America. The Atlantic, (March). Retrieved from http://www.theatlantic.com/magazine/archive/2010/03/how-a-new-jobless-era-will-transform-america/7919/

Rifkin, J. (1995). The end of work : the decline of the global labor force and the dawn of the post-market era. New York: G.P. Putnam’s Sons.

Sands, P. (2016). East West Street : on the origins of genocide and crimes against humanity. New York, NY: Alfred A. Knopf.

Schick, T., & Vaughn, L. (2013). Doing philosophy : an introduction through thought experiments (5th ed.). New York: McGraw-Hill.

Shweder, R. A., Much, N. C., Mahapatra, M., & Park, L. (1997). The ‘‘big three’’of morality (autonomy, community and divinity) and the ‘‘big three’’explanations of suffering. In A. M. Brandt & P. Rozin (Eds.), Morality and health (pp. 119-169). New York: Routledge.

Susskind, R., & Susskind, D. (2015). The future of the professions: How technology will transform the work of human experts. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

Waldron, J. (2012). The harm in hate speech. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

Michael H.G. Hoffmann

m.hoffmann@gatech.edu)

 Last update: January 4, 2018

Login Log into the Reflect Platform

Registration Register here.

(Only for new instructors or project managers. Students and team members will get an email to activate their account)

Contact us!

Supported by Cyberlearning and Future Learning Technologies, Award 1623419.

Contact the Institute

Directory

Offices

Campus Map

Apply

Support / Give

Log in

Georgia Institute of TechnologyNorth Avenue, Atlanta, GA 30332

404-894-2000

Emergency Information

Legal & Privacy Information

Human Trafficking Notice

Accessibility

Accountability

Accreditation

Employment

©2024 Georgia Institute of Technology

Ethical concerns mount as AI takes bigger decision-making role — Harvard Gazette

Ethical concerns mount as AI takes bigger decision-making role — Harvard Gazette

FindingsCampus & CommunityHealthScience & TechNation & WorldArts & CultureWork & Economy

Menu

Sections

FindingsCampus & CommunityHealthScience & TechNation & WorldArts & CultureWork & Economy

Featured Topics

“Rise of the Machines?”Housing DayInterim provostEvents

Featured series

Wondering

A series of random questions answered by Harvard experts.

Explore the Gazette

EventsArticle archiveAbout usNews+Podcast

Read the latest

Fed delivers good news overall on economy

Studying ‘why women are interesting, and men are boring’

Confused about changes in tipping customs? You’re not alone.

For Media & JournalistsAthletics News & ScoresDigital AccessibilityPrivacy PolicyTrademark

Search

Search the Harvard GazetteGo

“Rise of the Machines?”Housing DayInterim provostEvents

Illustration by Ben Boothman

Work & Economy

Great promise but potential for peril

Christina Pazzanese

Harvard Staff Writer

October 26, 2020

long read

Ethical concerns mount as AI takes bigger decision-making role in more industries

Second in a four-part series that taps the expertise of the Harvard community to examine the promise and potential pitfalls of the rising age of artificial intelligence and machine learning, and how to humanize them.

For decades, artificial intelligence, or AI, was the engine of high-level STEM research. Most consumers became aware of the technology’s power and potential through internet platforms like Google and Facebook, and retailer Amazon. Today, AI is essential across a vast array of industries, including health care, banking, retail, and manufacturing.

Also in the series

Science & Tech

Trailblazing initiative marries ethics, tech

long read

Health

AI revolution in medicine

long read

Science & Tech

Imagine a world in which AI is in your home, at work, everywhere

9 min read

But its game-changing promise to do things like improve efficiency, bring down costs, and accelerate research and development has been tempered of late with worries that these complex, opaque systems may do more societal harm than economic good. With virtually no U.S. government oversight, private companies use AI software to make determinations about health and medicine, employment, creditworthiness, and even criminal justice without having to answer for how they’re ensuring that programs aren’t encoded, consciously or unconsciously, with structural biases.

Its growing appeal and utility are undeniable. Worldwide business spending on AI is expected to hit $50 billion this year and $110 billion annually by 2024, even after the global economic slump caused by the COVID-19 pandemic, according to a forecast released in August by technology research firm IDC. Retail and banking industries spent the most this year, at more than $5 billion each. The company expects the media industry and federal and central governments will invest most heavily between 2018 and 2023 and predicts that AI will be “the disrupting influence changing entire industries over the next decade.”

“Virtually every big company now has multiple AI systems and counts the deployment of AI as integral to their strategy,” said Joseph Fuller, professor of management practice at Harvard Business School, who co-leads Managing the Future of Work, a research project that studies, in part, the development and implementation of AI, including machine learning, robotics, sensors, and industrial automation, in business and the work world.

Early on, it was popularly assumed that the future of AI would involve the automation of simple repetitive tasks requiring low-level decision-making. But AI has rapidly grown in sophistication, owing to more powerful computers and the compilation of huge data sets. One branch, machine learning, notable for its ability to sort and analyze massive amounts of data and to learn over time, has transformed countless fields, including education.

Firms now use AI to manage sourcing of materials and products from suppliers and to integrate vast troves of information to aid in strategic decision-making, and because of its capacity to process data so quickly, AI tools are helping to minimize time in the pricey trial-and-error of product development — a critical advance for an industry like pharmaceuticals, where it costs $1 billion to bring a new pill to market, Fuller said.

Health care experts see many possible uses for AI, including with billing and processing necessary paperwork. And medical professionals expect that the biggest, most immediate impact will be in analysis of data, imaging, and diagnosis. Imagine, they say, having the ability to bring all of the medical knowledge available on a disease to any given treatment decision.

In employment, AI software culls and processes resumes and analyzes job interviewees’ voice and facial expressions in hiring and driving the growth of what’s known as “hybrid” jobs. Rather than replacing employees, AI takes on important technical tasks of their work, like routing for package delivery trucks, which potentially frees workers to focus on other responsibilities, making them more productive and therefore more valuable to employers. 

“It’s allowing them to do more stuff better, or to make fewer errors, or to capture their expertise and disseminate it more effectively in the organization,” said Fuller, who has studied the effects and attitudes of workers who have lost or are likeliest to lose their jobs to AI.

“Can smart machines outthink us, or are certain elements of human judgment indispensable in deciding some of the most important things in life?”

— Michael Sandel, political philosopher and Anne T. and Robert M. Bass Professor of Government

Stephanie Mitchell/Harvard file photo

Though automation is here to stay, the elimination of entire job categories, like highway toll-takers who were replaced by sensors because of AI’s proliferation, is not likely, according to Fuller.

“What we’re going to see is jobs that require human interaction, empathy, that require applying judgment to what the machine is creating [will] have robustness,” he said.

While big business already has a huge head start, small businesses could also potentially be transformed by AI, says Karen Mills ’75, M.B.A. ’77, who ran the U.S. Small Business Administration from 2009 to 2013. With half the country employed by small businesses before the COVID-19 pandemic, that could have major implications for the national economy over the long haul.

Rather than hamper small businesses, the technology could give their owners detailed new insights into sales trends, cash flow, ordering, and other important financial information in real time so they can better understand how the business is doing and where problem areas might loom without having to hire anyone, become a financial expert, or spend hours laboring over the books every week, Mills said.

One area where AI could “completely change the game” is lending, where access to capital is difficult in part because banks often struggle to get an accurate picture of a small business’s viability and creditworthiness.

“It’s much harder to look inside a business operation and know what’s going on” than it is to assess an individual, she said.

Information opacity makes the lending process laborious and expensive for both would-be borrowers and lenders, and applications are designed to analyze larger companies or those who’ve already borrowed, a built-in disadvantage for certain types of businesses and for historically underserved borrowers, like women and minority business owners, said Mills, a senior fellow at HBS.

But with AI-powered software pulling information from a business’s bank account, taxes, and online bookkeeping records and comparing it with data from thousands of similar businesses, even small community banks will be able to make informed assessments in minutes, without the agony of paperwork and delays, and, like blind auditions for musicians, without fear that any inequity crept into the decision-making.

“All of that goes away,” she said.

A veneer of objectivity

Not everyone sees blue skies on the horizon, however. Many worry whether the coming age of AI will bring new, faster, and frictionless ways to discriminate and divide at scale.

“Part of the appeal of algorithmic decision-making is that it seems to offer an objective way of overcoming human subjectivity, bias, and prejudice,” said political philosopher Michael Sandel, Anne T. and Robert M. Bass Professor of Government. “But we are discovering that many of the algorithms that decide who should get parole, for example, or who should be presented with employment opportunities or housing … replicate and embed the biases that already exist in our society.”

“If we’re not thoughtful and careful, we’re going to end up with redlining again.”

— Karen Mills, senior fellow at the Business School and head of the U.S. Small Business Administration from 2009 to 2013

Jon Chase/Harvard file photo

AI presents three major areas of ethical concern for society: privacy and surveillance, bias and discrimination, and perhaps the deepest, most difficult philosophical question of the era, the role of human judgment, said Sandel, who teaches a course in the moral, social, and political implications of new technologies.

“Debates about privacy safeguards and about how to overcome bias in algorithmic decision-making in sentencing, parole, and employment practices are by now familiar,” said Sandel, referring to conscious and unconscious prejudices of program developers and those built into datasets used to train the software. “But we’ve not yet wrapped our minds around the hardest question: Can smart machines outthink us, or are certain elements of human judgment indispensable in deciding some of the most important things in life?”

Panic over AI suddenly injecting bias into everyday life en masse is overstated, says Fuller. First, the business world and the workplace, rife with human decision-making, have always been riddled with “all sorts” of biases that prevent people from making deals or landing contracts and jobs.

When calibrated carefully and deployed thoughtfully, resume-screening software allows a wider pool of applicants to be considered than could be done otherwise, and should minimize the potential for favoritism that comes with human gatekeepers, Fuller said.

Sandel disagrees. “AI not only replicates human biases, it confers on these biases a kind of scientific credibility. It makes it seem that these predictions and judgments have an objective status,” he said.

In the world of lending, algorithm-driven decisions do have a potential “dark side,” Mills said. As machines learn from data sets they’re fed, chances are “pretty high” they may replicate many of the banking industry’s past failings that resulted in systematic disparate treatment of African Americans and other marginalized consumers.

“If we’re not thoughtful and careful, we’re going to end up with redlining again,” she said.

A highly regulated industry, banks are legally on the hook if the algorithms they use to evaluate loan applications end up inappropriately discriminating against classes of consumers, so those “at the top levels” in the field are “very focused” right now on this issue, said Mills, who closely studies the rapid changes in financial technology, or “fintech.”

“They really don’t want to discriminate. They want to get access to capital to the most creditworthy borrowers,” she said. “That’s good business for them, too.”

Oversight overwhelmed

Given its power and expected ubiquity, some argue that the use of AI should be tightly regulated. But there’s little consensus on how that should be done and who should make the rules.

Thus far, companies that develop or use AI systems largely self-police, relying on existing laws and market forces, like negative reactions from consumers and shareholders or the demands of highly-prized AI technical talent to keep them in line.

“There’s no businessperson on the planet at an enterprise of any size that isn’t concerned about this and trying to reflect on what’s going to be politically, legally, regulatorily, [or] ethically acceptable,” said Fuller.

Firms already consider their own potential liability from misuse before a product launch, but it’s not realistic to expect companies to anticipate and prevent every possible unintended consequence of their product, he said.

Few think the federal government is up to the job, or will ever be.

“The regulatory bodies are not equipped with the expertise in artificial intelligence to engage in [oversight] without some real focus and investment,” said Fuller, noting the rapid rate of technological change means even the most informed legislators can’t keep pace. Requiring every new product using AI to be prescreened for potential social harms is not only impractical, but would create a huge drag on innovation.

“I wouldn’t have a central AI group that has a division that does cars, I would have the car people have a division of people who are really good at AI.”

— Jason Furman, a professor of the practice of economic policy at the Kennedy School and a former top economic adviser to President Barack Obama

Rose Lincoln/Harvard Staff Photographer

Jason Furman, a professor of the practice of economic policy at Harvard Kennedy School, agrees that government regulators need “a much better technical understanding of artificial intelligence to do that job well,” but says they could do it.

Existing bodies like the National Highway Transportation Safety Association, which oversees vehicle safety, for example, could handle potential AI issues in autonomous vehicles rather than a single watchdog agency, he said.

“I wouldn’t have a central AI group that has a division that does cars, I would have the car people have a division of people who are really good at AI,” said Furman, a former top economic adviser to President Barack Obama.

Though keeping AI regulation within industries does leave open the possibility of co-opted enforcement, Furman said industry-specific panels would be far more knowledgeable about the overarching technology of which AI is simply one piece, making for more thorough oversight.

While the European Union already has rigorous data-privacy laws and the European Commission is considering a formal regulatory framework for ethical use of AI, the U.S. government has historically been late when it comes to tech regulation.

“I think we should’ve started three decades ago, but better late than never,” said Furman, who thinks there needs to be a “greater sense of urgency” to make lawmakers act.

Business leaders “can’t have it both ways,” refusing responsibility for AI’s harmful consequences while also fighting government oversight, Sandel maintains.

More like this

Science & Tech

The robots are coming, but relax

4 min read

Science & Tech

The good, bad, and scary of the Internet of Things

6 min read

Nation & World

Paving the way for self-driving cars

long read

“The problem is these big tech companies are neither self-regulating, nor subject to adequate government regulation. I think there needs to be more of both,” he said, later adding: “We can’t assume that market forces by themselves will sort it out. That’s a mistake, as we’ve seen with Facebook and other tech giants.”

Last fall, Sandel taught “Tech Ethics,” a popular new Gen Ed course with Doug Melton, co-director of Harvard’s Stem Cell Institute. As in his legendary “Justice” course, students consider and debate the big questions about new technologies, everything from gene editing and robots to privacy and surveillance.

“Companies have to think seriously about the ethical dimensions of what they’re doing and we, as democratic citizens, have to educate ourselves about tech and its social and ethical implications — not only to decide what the regulations should be, but also to decide what role we want big tech and social media to play in our lives,” said Sandel.

Doing that will require a major educational intervention, both at Harvard and in higher education more broadly, he said.

“We have to enable all students to learn enough about tech and about the ethical implications of new technologies so that when they are running companies or when they are acting as democratic citizens, they will be able to ensure that technology serves human purposes rather than undermines a decent civic life.”

Next: The AI revolution in medicine may lift personalized treatment, fill gaps in access to care, and cut red tape. Yet risks abound.

Share this article

Share on Facebook

Share on LinkedIn

Email article

Print/PDF

You might like

Work & Economy

Fed delivers good news overall on economy

Economist Jeffrey Frankel says the central bank held off on easing interest rates, but signs point to soft landing

9 min read

Work & Economy

Studying ‘why women are interesting, and men are boring’

Nobel laureate Claudia Goldin recounts pioneering career spent tracing major part of U.S. workforce, economy hidden in plain sight

Part of the

Experience

series

long read

Work & Economy

Confused about changes in tipping customs? You’re not alone.

Customer relations expert says technologies, COVID changed behaviors across the U.S.

7 min read

Trending

Health

Potential link to an everyday food in cancer findings

Oleic acid, key component of olive oil, implicated in metastasis — but investigators emphasize the need for more clarity

5 min read

Arts & Culture

So what exactly makes Taylor Swift so great?

Experts weigh in on pop superstar's cultural and financial impact as her tours and albums continue to break records.

long read

Health

Time to finally stop worrying about COVID?

Chan School’s William Hanage says CDC may have eased some recommendations, but vulnerable populations remain just that

8 min read

Sections

FindingsCampus & CommunityHealthScience & TechNation & WorldArts & CultureWork & Economy

Explore the Gazette

EventsArticle archiveAbout usNews+Podcast

Our recent series

Fixing the Constitution

Many analysts and citizens believe that the Constitution, more than 230 years old, is out of touch with contemporary America. We asked five scholars to isolate the problem they’d attack first.

Life | Work

A series focused on the personal side of Harvard research and teaching.

Follow us on

Instagram

LinkedIn

TikTok

Facebook

YouTube

Email

For Media & JournalistsAthletics News & ScoresDigital AccessibilityPrivacy PolicyTrademark

Just a moment...

a moment...Enable JavaScript and cookies to continue

Ethics - Wikipedia

Ethics - Wikipedia

Jump to content

Main menu

Main menu

move to sidebar

hide

Navigation

Main pageContentsCurrent eventsRandom articleAbout WikipediaContact usDonate

Contribute

HelpLearn to editCommunity portalRecent changesUpload file

Search

Search

Create account

Log in

Personal tools

Create account Log in

Pages for logged out editors learn more

ContributionsTalk

Contents

move to sidebar

hide

(Top)

1Definition

2Normative ethics

Toggle Normative ethics subsection

2.1Consequentialism

2.1.1Types

2.1.2Utilitarianism

2.2Deontology

2.2.1Agent-centered and patient-centered

2.2.2Kantianism

2.2.3Divine command theory, contractualism, and discourse ethics

2.3Virtue ethics

2.4Others

3Applied ethics

Toggle Applied ethics subsection

3.1Bioethics

3.2Business and professional ethics

3.3Others

4Metaethics

Toggle Metaethics subsection

4.1Basic concepts

4.2Realism, relativism, and nihilism

4.2.1Naturalism and non-naturalism

4.3Cognitivism and non-cognitivism

4.4Moral knowledge

4.5Moral motivation

5Related fields

Toggle Related fields subsection

5.1Value theory

5.2Moral psychology

5.3Descriptive ethics

6History

7See also

8References

Toggle References subsection

8.1Notes

8.2Citations

8.3Sources

9External links

Toggle the table of contents

Ethics

136 languages

AfrikaansAlemannischአማርኛअंगिकाالعربيةAragonésAsturianuAzərbaycancaتۆرکجهবাংলাBân-lâm-gúБашҡортсаБеларускаяБеларуская (тарашкевіца)БългарскиBoarischBosanskiCatalàČeštinaCymraegDanskDeutschEestiΕλληνικάEspañolEsperantoEuskaraفارسیFiji HindiFøroysktFrançaisFryskGaeilgeGalego贛語Gungbe한국어Հայերենहिन्दीHrvatskiIlokanoBahasa IndonesiaInterlinguaÍslenskaItalianoעבריתJawaKabɩyɛქართულიҚазақшаKernowekKiswahiliKreyòl ayisyenKriyòl gwiyannenKurdîКыргызчаLadinລາວLatinaLatviešuLëtzebuergeschЛезгиLietuviųLimburgsLingua Franca NovaLa .lojban.LugandaMagyarमैथिलीМакедонскиMalagasyമലയാളംमराठीმარგალურიBahasa MelayuMirandésМонголမြန်မာဘာသာNa Vosa VakavitiNederlandsनेपाली日本語НохчийнNordfriiskNorsk bokmålNorsk nynorskOccitanOromooOʻzbekcha / ўзбекчаਪੰਜਾਬੀپنجابیپښتوPatoisភាសាខ្មែរPiemontèisPlattdüütschPolskiPortuguêsQaraqalpaqshaQırımtatarcaRomânăРусиньскыйРусскийСаха тылаShqipSicilianuසිංහලSimple EnglishSlovenčinaSlovenščinaکوردیСрпски / srpskiSrpskohrvatski / српскохрватскиSundaSuomiSvenskaTagalogதமிழ்Татарча / tatarçaไทยТоҷикӣTürkçeУкраїнськаاردوVahcuenghVepsän kel’Tiếng ViệtWinaray吴语Xitsongaייִדיש粵語ZazakiŽemaitėška中文Tolışi

Edit links

ArticleTalk

English

ReadEditView history

Tools

Tools

move to sidebar

hide

Actions

ReadEditView history

General

What links hereRelated changesUpload fileSpecial pagesPermanent linkPage informationCite this pageGet shortened URLDownload QR codeWikidata item

Print/export

Download as PDFPrintable version

In other projects

Wikimedia CommonsWikibooksWikiquote

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Philosophical study of morality

For other uses, see Ethics (disambiguation).

Ethics is concerned with the moral status of entities, for example, whether an act is obligatory or prohibited.[1]

Ethics or moral philosophy is the philosophical study of moral phenomena. It investigates normative questions about what people ought to do or which behavior is morally right. It is usually divided into three major fields: normative ethics, applied ethics, and metaethics.

Normative ethics discovers and justifies universal principles that govern how people should act in any situation. According to consequentialists, an act is right if it leads to the best consequences. Deontologists hold that morality consists in fulfilling duties, like telling the truth and keeping promises. Virtue theorists see the manifestation of virtues, like courage and compassion, as the fundamental principle of morality. Applied ethics examines concrete ethical problems in real-life situations, for example, by exploring the moral implications of the universal principles discovered in normative ethics within a specific domain. Bioethics studies moral issues associated with living organisms including humans, animals, and plants. Business ethics investigates how ethical principles apply to corporations, while professional ethics focuses on what is morally required of members of different professions. Metaethics is a metatheory that examines the underlying assumptions and concepts of ethics. It asks whether moral facts have mind-independent existence, whether moral statements can be true, how it is possible to acquire moral knowledge, and how moral judgments motivate people.

Ethics is closely connected to value theory, which studies what value is and what types of value there are. Moral psychology is a related empirical field and investigates psychological processes involved in morality, such as moral reasoning and the formation of moral character. Descriptive ethics provides value-neutral descriptions of the dominant moral codes and beliefs in different societies and considers their historical dimension.

The history of ethics started in the ancient period with the development of ethical principles and theories in ancient Egypt, India, China, and Greece. This period saw the emergence of ethical teachings associated with Hinduism, Buddhism, Confucianism, Daoism, and contributions of philosophers like Socrates and Aristotle. During the medieval period, ethical thought was strongly influenced by religious teachings. In the modern period, this focus shifted to a more secular approach concerned with moral experience, practical reason, and the consequences of actions. An influential development in the 20th century was the emergence of metaethics.

Definition [edit]

According to Aristotle, how to lead a good life is one of the central questions of ethics.[2]

Ethics, also referred to as moral philosophy, is the study of moral phenomena. It is one of the main branches of philosophy and investigates the nature of morality and the principles that govern the moral evaluation of conduct, character traits, and institutions. It examines what obligations people have, what behavior is right and wrong, and how to lead a good life. Some of its key questions are "How should one live?" and "What gives meaning to life?".[3]

The domain of morality is a normative field governing what people ought to do rather than what they actually do, what they want to do, or what social conventions require. As a rational and systematic field of inquiry, ethics studies practical reasons why people should act one way rather than another. Most ethical theories seek universal principles that express a general standpoint of what is objectively right and wrong.[4] In a slightly different sense, the term "ethics" can also refer to individual ethical theories in the form of a rational system of moral principles, such as Aristotelian ethics, and to a moral code that certain societies, social groups, or professions follow, as in Protestant work ethic and medical ethics.[5]

The terms "ethics" and "morality" are usually used interchangeably but some philosophers draw a distinction between the two. According to one view, morality is restricted to the question of what moral obligations people have while ethics is a wider term that takes additional considerations into account, such as what is good or how to lead a meaningful life. Another difference is that codes of conduct pertaining to specific areas, such as the business and environment, are usually termed "ethics" rather than morality, as in business ethics and environmental ethics.[6]

As a philosophical discipline, ethics is usually divided into normative ethics, applied ethics, and metaethics. Normative ethics tries to find and justify universal principles of moral conduct. Applied ethics examines the consequences of those principles in specific domains of practical life. Metaethics is a metatheory that studies underlying assumptions and concepts, such as what the nature of morality is and whether moral judgments can be objectively true.[7]

The English word ethics has its roots in the Ancient Greek word êthos (ἦθος) meaning "character, personal disposition". This word gave rise to the Ancient Greek word ēthikós (ἠθικός), which was translated into Latin as ethica and entered the English language in the 15th century through the Old French term éthique.[8]

Normative ethics[edit]

Main article: Normative ethics

Normative ethics is the philosophical study of ethical conduct and investigates the fundamental principles of morality. It asks questions like "How should one live?" and "How should people act?". Its main goal is to discover and justify general answers to these questions. To do so, it usually seeks universal or domain-independent principles that determine whether an act is right or wrong.[9] For example, given the particular impression that it is wrong to set a child on fire for fun, normative ethics aims to find more general principles that explain why this is the case, like the principle that one should not cause extreme suffering to the innocent, which may itself be explained in terms of a more general principle.[10] Many theories of normative ethics aim additionally to guide behavior by helping people make moral decisions.[11]

Theories in normative ethics state how people should act or what kind of behavior is correct. They do not aim to describe how people normally act, what moral beliefs ordinary people have, how these beliefs change over time, or what ethical codes are upheld in certain social groups. These topics belong to descriptive ethics and are studied in fields like anthropology, sociology, and history rather than normative ethics.[12] Another contrast is with applied ethics, which investigates right moral conduct within a specific domain rather than general moral principles studied by normative ethics.[13]

Some systems of normative ethics arrive at a single principle that covers all possible cases while others encompass a small set of basic rules that address all or at least the most important moral considerations.[14] One difficulty for systems with several basic principles is that these principles may in some cases conflict with each other and lead to ethical dilemmas.[15]

Different theories in normative ethics suggest different principles as the foundation of morality. The three most influential schools of thought are consequentialism, deontology, and virtue ethics.[16] These schools are usually presented as exclusive alternatives but depending on how they are defined, they can overlap and do not necessarily exclude one another.[17] In some cases, they differ concerning which acts they see as right or wrong. In other cases, they recommend the same course of action but provide different justifications for why it is right.[18]

Consequentialism[edit]

Main article: Consequentialism

Consequentialism, also referred to as teleological ethics,[19][a] holds that morality depends on consequences. According to the most common view, an act is right if it brings about the best future. This means that there is no alternative course of action that has better consequences.[21] A key aspect of consequentialist theories is that they provide a characterization of what is good and then define what is right in terms of what is good.[22]

Consequentialists usually understand the consequences of an action in a very wide sense that includes the totality of its effects. This is based on the idea that actions make a difference to the world by bringing about a causal chain of events that would not have existed otherwise.[23] A core intuition behind consequentialism is that what matters is not the past but the future and that it should be shaped to result in the best possible outcome.[24]

The act itself is usually not seen as part of the consequences. This means that if an act has intrinsic value and disvalue, it is not included as a relevant factor. Some consequentialists try to avoid this complication by including the act itself as part of the consequences. A related approach is to characterize consequentialism not in terms of consequences but in terms of outcomes with outcome being defined as the act together with its consequences.[25]

Most forms of consequentialism are agent-neutral. This means that the value of consequences is assessed from a neutral perspective, i.e., acts should have consequences that are good in general and not just good for the agent. It is controversial whether agent-relative moral theories, like ethical egoism, should be considered as types of consequentialism.[26]

Types[edit]

There are many different types of consequentialism. They differ from each other based on what type of entity they evaluate, how they determine whether a consequence is good, and what consequences they take into consideration.[27] Most theories assess the moral value of acts. However, consequentialism can also be used to evaluate motives, character traits, rules, and policies.[28]

Many consequentialists assess the value of consequences based on whether they promote happiness or suffering. But there are also alternative evaluative principles, such as desire satisfaction, autonomy, freedom, knowledge, friendship, beauty, and self-perfection.[29] Some forms of consequentialism hold that there is only a single source of value.[30] The most prominent among them is utilitarianism, which states that the moral value of acts only depends on the pleasure they cause.[31] An alternative approach is to hold that there are many different sources of value. According to this view, all sources of value contribute to one overall value.[30] Traditionally, consequentialists were only concerned with the sum total of value or the aggregate good. A more recently developed view is that the distribution of value also matters. It states, for example, that an equal distribution of goods is better than an unequal distribution even if the aggregate good is the same.[32]

There are various disagreements about what consequences should be assessed. An important distinction is between act and rule consequentialism. According to act consequentialism, the consequences of an act determine the moral value of this act. This means that there is a direct relation between the consequences of an act and its moral value. Rule consequentialism, by contrast, holds that an act is right if it follows a certain set of rules. Rule consequentialism uses considerations of consequences to determine which rules should be followed: people should follow the rules that have the best consequences in a community that accepts them. This implies that the relation between an act and its consequences is indirect. For example, if a prohibition to lie is part of the best rules then, according to rule consequentialism, a person should not lie even in a particular case where lying would result in the best possible consequences.[33]

Another disagreement on the level of consequences is between actual and expected consequentialism. According to the traditional view, only the actual consequences of an act affect its moral value. One difficulty of this view is that many consequences cannot be known in advance. This means that in some cases, even well-planned and intentioned acts are morally wrong if they inadvertently lead to negative outcomes. An alternative perspective states that what matters are not the actual consequences but the expected consequences. This view takes into account that when deciding what to do, people have to rely on their very limited knowledge of the total consequences of their actions. According to this view, a course of action has positive moral value despite leading to an overall negative outcome if it had the highest expected value, for example, because the negative outcome could not be anticipated or was very unlikely.[34]

Another difference is between maximizing and satisficing consequentialism. According to maximizing consequentialism, only the best possible act is morally permitted. This means that acts with positive consequences are wrong if there are alternatives with even better consequences. One criticism of maximizing consequentialism is that it demands too much by requiring that people do significantly more than they are socially expected to. For example, if the best action for someone with a good salary would be to donate 70% of their income to charity, it would be morally wrong for them to only donate 65%. Satisficing consequentialism, by contrast, only requires that an act is "good enough" even if it is not the best possible alternative. According to this view, it is possible to do more than one is morally required to do, a state known as supererogation.[35]

Mohism in ancient Chinese philosophy is one of the earliest forms of consequentialism. It argues that political action should promote justice as a means to increase the welfare of the people.[36]

Utilitarianism[edit]

Main article: Utilitarianism

The most well-known form of consequentialism is utilitarianism. In its classical form, it is an act consequentialism that sees happiness as the only source of intrinsic value. This means that an act is morally right if it produces "the greatest good for the greatest number" by increasing happiness and reducing suffering. Utilitarians do not deny that other things also have value, like health, friendship, and knowledge. However, they deny that these things have intrinsic value. Instead, they hold that they have extrinsic value because they affect happiness and suffering. In this regard, they are desirable as a means but, unlike happiness, not desirable as an end.[37] The view that pleasure is the only thing with intrinsic value is called ethical or evaluative hedonism.[38]

Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill are the founding fathers of utilitarianism.

Utilitarianism was initially formulated by Jeremy Bentham and further developed by John Stuart Mill. Bentham introduced the hedonic calculus to assess the value of consequences. Two key aspects of the hedonic calculus are the intensity and the duration of pleasure. According to this view, a pleasurable experience has a high value if it has a high intensity and lasts for a long time. Some critics of Bentham's utilitarianism argued that it is a "philosophy of swine" whose focus on the intensity of pleasure promotes an immoral lifestyle centered around indulgence in sensory pleasures. Mill responded to this criticism by distinguishing between higher and lower pleasures. He stated that higher pleasures, like the intellectual pleasure of reading a book, are more valuable than lower pleasures, like the sensory pleasure of food and drink, even if their intensity and duration are the same.[39] Today, there are many variations of utilitarianism, including the difference between act and rule utilitarianism and between maximizing and satisficing utilitarianism.[40]

Deontology[edit]

Main article: Deontology

Deontology assesses the moral rightness of actions based on a set of norms or principles. These norms describe certain requirements or duties that all actions need to follow.[41] They may include requirements like to tell the truth, keep promises, and not intentionally harm others.[42] Unlike consequentialists, deontologists hold that the validity of general moral principles does not depend on their consequences. They state that these principles should be followed in every case since they express how actions are inherently right or wrong. For example, according to David Ross, it is wrong to break a promise even if no harm comes from it.[43] In this regard, deontologists often allow that there is a gap between what is right and what is good.[22] Many tend to follow a negative approach by holding that certain acts are forbidden under any circumstances.[44]

Agent-centered and patient-centered[edit]

Agent-centered deontological theories focus on the role of moral agency and following one's duties. They are often interested in the motives and intentions for which people act and emphasize the importance of doing something for the right reasons. They are often agent-relative, meaning that the reasons for which people should act depend on personal circumstances. For example, a parent has a special obligation to their child while a stranger does not have this kind of obligation toward a child they do not know. Patient-centered theories, by contrast, emphasize the rights of the people affected by the action. An example is the requirement to treat other people as ends and not merely as a means to an end.[45] This requirement can be used to argue, for example, that it is wrong to kill a person against their will even if this act would save the life of several others. Patient-centered deontological theories are usually agent-neutral, meaning that they apply equally to everyone in a situation, regardless of their specific role or position.[46]

Kantianism[edit]

Main article: Kantian ethics

Immanuel Kant is one of the most well-known deontologists.[47] He insists that moral action should not be guided by situation-dependent means-end reasoning to achieve some kind of fixed good, such as happiness. Instead, he argues that there are certain moral principles that apply to every situation independent of means-end relations. Kant uses the term categorical imperative for these principles and holds that they are non-empirical and universal laws that have their source in the structure of practical reason and apply to all rational agents. According to Kant, to act morally is to act in accordance with reason as expressed by these principles.[48] He sees immoral actions as irrational by going against the fundamental principles of practical reason.[49]

Kant provided several formulations of the categorical imperative. One emphasizes the universal nature of reason and states that people should only follow maxims that could become universal laws applicable to everyone. This means that the person would want everyone else also to follow this maxim. Another formulation states that one should treat other people always as ends in themselves and never as mere means to an end. This formulation focuses on respecting and valuing other people for their own sake rather than using them in the pursuit of personal goals.[50]

In either case, Kant holds that what matters is to have a good will. A person has a good will if they respect the moral law and form their intentions and motives in accordance with it. According to Kant, actions motivated in such a way are unconditionally good, meaning that they are good even in cases where they result in undesirable consequences.[51]

Divine command theory, contractualism, and discourse ethics[edit]

Main articles: Divine command theory, Contractualism, and Discourse ethics

Divine command theory sees God as the source of morality. It states that moral laws are divine commands and that to act morally is to obey and follow God's will. While all divine command theorists agree that morality depends on God, there are disagreements about the precise content of the divine commands, and theorists belonging to different religions tend to propose different moral laws.[52] For example, Christian and Jewish divine command theorists may argue that the Ten Commandments express God's will[53] while Muslims may reserve this role for the teachings of the Quran.[54]

Contractualists reject the reference to God as the source of morality and argue instead that morality is based on an explicit or implicit social contract between humans. They state that actual or hypothetical consent to this contract is the source of moral norms and duties. To determine which duties people have, contractualists often rely on a thought experiment about what rational people under ideal circumstances would agree on. For example, if they would agree that people should not lie then there is a moral obligation to refrain from lying. Because of its reliance on consent, contractualism is often understood as a patient-centered form of deontology.[55][b]

According to discourse ethics, as formulated by Jürgen Habermas, moral norms are justified by a rational discourse within society.

Discourse ethics also focuses on social agreement on moral norms but holds that this agreement is based on communicative rationality. It aims to arrive at moral norms for pluralistic modern societies that encompass a diversity of viewpoints. A universal moral norm is seen as valid if all rational discourse participants do or would approve. This way, morality is not imposed by a single moral authority but arises from the moral discourse within society. This discourse should follow certain requirements characteristic of an ideal speech situation. One of its key aspects is that discourse participants are free to voice their different opinions without coercion but are at the same time required to justify them using rational argumentation.[57]

Virtue ethics[edit]

Main article: Virtue ethics

The main concern of virtue ethics is how virtues are expressed in actions. As such, it is neither directly interested in the consequences of actions nor in universal moral duties.[58] Virtues are positive character traits, like honesty, courage, kindness, and compassion. They are usually understood as dispositions to feel, decide, and act in a certain manner by being wholeheartedly committed to this manner. Virtues contrast with vices, which are their harmful counterparts.[59]

Virtue theorists usually hold that the mere possession of virtues by itself is not sufficient. Instead, people should manifest virtues in their actions. An important factor in this regard is the practical wisdom, also referred to as phronesis, of knowing, when, how, and which virtue to express. For example, a lack of practical wisdom may lead courageous people to perform morally wrong actions by taking unnecessary risks that should better be avoided.[60]

Different types of virtue ethics differ concerning how they understand virtues and their role in practical life. Eudaimonism is the classical view and draws a close relation between virtuous behavior and happiness. It states that people flourish by living a virtuous life. Eudaimonist theories often hold that virtues are positive potentials residing in human nature and that actualizing these potentials results in leading a good and happy life.[61] Agent-based theories, by contrast, see happiness only as a side effect and focus instead on the motivational and dispositional characteristics that are expressed while acting. This is often combined with the idea that one can learn from exceptional individuals what those characteristics are.[61] Feminist ethics of care are another form of virtue ethics. They emphasize the importance of interpersonal relationships and hold that benevolence by caring for the well-being of others is one of the key virtues.[62]

Philippa Foot was one of the philosophers responsible for the revival of virtue ethics in the 20th century.

Influential schools of virtue ethics in ancient philosophy were Aristotelianism and Stoicism. According to Aristotle, each virtue is a golden mean between two types of vices: excess and deficiency. For example, courage is a virtue that lies between the deficient state of cowardice and the excessive state of recklessness. Aristotle held that virtuous action leads to happiness and makes people flourish in life.[63] The Stoics believed that people can achieve happiness through virtue alone. They stated that people are happy if they are in a peaceful state of mind that is free from emotional disturbances. They advocated rationality and self-mastery to achieve this state.[64] In the 20th century, virtue ethics experienced a resurgence thanks to philosophers such as Elizabeth Anscombe, Philippa Foot, Alasdair MacIntyre, and Martha Nussbaum.[65]

Others[edit]

There are many other schools of normative ethics in addition to the three main traditions. Pragmatist ethics focuses on the role of practice and holds that one of the key tasks of ethics is to solve practical problems in concrete situations. It has certain similarities to utilitarianism and its focus on consequences but concentrates more on how morality is embedded in and relative to social and cultural contexts. Pragmatists tend to give more importance to habits than to conscious deliberation and understand morality as a habit that should be shaped in the right way.[66]

Postmodern ethics agrees with pragmatist ethics about the cultural relativity of morality. It rejects the idea that there are objective moral principles that apply universally to all cultures and traditions. It asserts that there is no one coherent ethical code since morality itself is irrational and humans are morally ambivalent beings.[67]

The practices of compassion and loving-kindness are key elements of Buddhist ethics.

Ethical egoism is the view that people should act in their self-interest or that an action is morally right if the person acts for their own benefit. It differs from psychological egoism, which states that people actually follow their self-interest without claiming that they should do so. Ethical egoists may act in accordance with commonly accepted moral expectations and benefit other people, for example, by keeping promises, helping friends, and cooperating with others. However, they do so only as a means to promote their self-interest. Ethical egoism is often criticized as an immoral and contradictory position.[68]

Normative ethics has a central place in most religions. Key aspects of Jewish ethics are to follow the 613 commandments of God according to the Mitzvah duty found in the Torah and to take responsibility for societal welfare.[69] Christian ethics puts less emphasis on following precise laws and teaches instead the practice of self-less love, such as the Great Commandment to "love your neighbor as yourself".[70] The Five Pillars of Islam constitute a basic framework of Muslim ethics and focus on the practice of faith, prayer, charity, fasting during Ramadan, and pilgrimage to Mecca.[71] Buddhists emphasize the importance of compassion and loving-kindness towards all sentient entities.[72] A similar outlook is found in Jainism, which has non-violence as its principal virtue.[73] Duty is a central aspect of Hindu ethics and is about fulfilling social obligations, which may vary depending on a person's social class and stage of life.[74] Confucianism places great emphasis on harmony in society and sees benevolence as a key virtue.[75] Taoism extends the importance of living in harmony to the whole world and teaches that people should practice effortless action by following the natural flow of the universe.[76]

Applied ethics[edit]

Main article: Applied ethics

Applied ethics, also known as practical ethics,[77] is the branch of ethics and applied philosophy that examines concrete moral problems encountered in real-life situations. Unlike normative ethics, it is not concerned with discovering or justifying universal ethical principles. Instead, it studies how those principles can be applied to specific domains of practical life, what consequences they have in these fields, and whether other considerations are relevant.[78]

One of the difficulties of applied ethics is to determine how to apply general ethical principles to concrete practical situations, like medical procedures.

One of the main challenges of applied ethics is to breach the gap between abstract universal theories and their application to concrete situations. For example, an in-depth understanding of Kantianism or utilitarianism is usually not sufficient to decide how to analyze the moral implications of a medical procedure. One reason is that it may not be clear how the procedure affects the Kantian requirement of respecting everyone's personhood and what the consequences of the procedure are in terms of the greatest good for the greatest number.[79] This difficulty is particularly relevant to applied ethicists who employ a top-down methodology by starting from universal ethical principles and applying them to particular cases within a specific domain.[80] A different approach is to use a bottom-up methodology, which relies on many observations of particular cases to arrive at an understanding of the moral principles relevant to this particular domain.[81] In either case, inquiry into applied ethics is often triggered by ethical dilemmas to solve cases in which a person is subject to conflicting moral requirements.[82]

Applied ethics covers issues pertaining to both the private sphere, like right conduct in the family and close relationships, and the public sphere, like moral problems posed by new technologies and international duties toward future generations.[83] Major branches include bioethics, business ethics, and professional ethics. There are many other branches and their domains of inquiry often overlap.[84]

Bioethics[edit]

Main article: Bioethics

Bioethics is a wide field that covers moral problems associated with living organisms and biological disciplines.[85] A key problem in bioethics concerns the moral status of entities and to what extent this status depends on features such as consciousness, being able to feel pleasure and pain, rationality, and personhood. These differences concern, for example, how to treat non-living entities like rocks and non-sentient entities like plants in contrast to animals and whether humans have a different moral status than other animals.[86] According to anthropocentrism, only humans have a basic moral status. This implies that all other entities only have a derivative moral status to the extent that they affect human life. Sentientism, by contrast, extends an inherent moral status to all sentient beings. Further positions include biocentrism, which also covers non-sentient lifeforms, and ecocentrism, which states that all of nature has a basic moral status.[87]

Bioethics is relevant to various aspects of life and to many professions. It covers a wide range of moral problems associated with topics like abortion, cloning, stem cell research, euthanasia, suicide, animal testing, intensive animal farming, nuclear waste, and air pollution.[88]

Bioethics can be divided into medical ethics, animal ethics, and environmental ethics based on whether the ethical problems relate to humans, other animals, or nature in general.[89] Medical ethics is the oldest branch of bioethics and has its origins in the Hippocratic Oath, which establishes ethical guidelines for medical practitioners like a prohibition to harm the patient.[90] A central topic in medical ethics concerns issues associated with the beginning and the end of life. One debate focuses on the question of whether a fetus is a full-fledged person with all the rights associated with this status. For example, some proponents of this view argue that abortion is a form of murder.[91] In relation to the end of life, there are ethical dilemmas concerning whether a person has a right to end their own life in cases of terminal illness and whether a medical practitioner may assist them in doing so.[92] Other topics in medical ethics include medical confidentiality, informed consent, research on human beings, organ transplantation, and access to healthcare.[90]

Harm done to animals is a particular concern in animal ethics, for example, as a result of intensive animal farming.

Animal ethics examines how humans should treat other animals. An influential consideration in this field emphasizes the importance of animal welfare while arguing that humans should avoid or minimize the harm done to animals. There is wide agreement that it is wrong to torture animals for fun. The situation is more complicated in cases where harm is inflicted on animals as a side effect of the pursuit of human interests. This happens, for example, during factory farming, when using animals as food, and for research experiments on animals.[93] A key topic in animal ethics is the formulation of animal rights. Animal rights theorists assert that animals have a certain moral status and that humans have an obligation to respect this status when interacting with them.[94] Examples of suggested animal rights include the right to life, the right to be free from unnecessary suffering, and the right to natural behavior in a suitable environment.[95]

Environmental ethics deals with moral problems relating to the natural environment including animals, plants, natural resources, and ecosystems. In its widest sense, it also covers the whole biosphere and the cosmos.[96] In the domain of agriculture, this concerns questions like under what circumstances it is acceptable to clear the vegetation of an area to use it for farming and the implications of using genetically modified crops.[97] On a wider scale, environmental ethics addresses the problem of global warming and how people are responsible for this both on an individual and a collective level. Environmental ethicists often promote sustainable practices and policies directed at protecting and conserving ecosystems and biodiversity.[98]

Business and professional ethics[edit]

Main articles: Business ethics and Professional ethics

Business ethics examines the moral implications of business conduct and investigates how ethical principles apply to corporations and organizations.[99] A key topic is corporate social responsibility, which is the responsibility of corporations to act in a manner that benefits society at large. Corporate social responsibility is a complex issue since many stakeholders are directly and indirectly involved in corporate decisions, such as the CEO, the board of directors, and the shareholders. A closely related topic concerns the question of whether corporations themselves, and not just their stakeholders, have moral agency.[100] Business ethics further examines the role of truthfulness, honesty, and fairness in business practices as well as the moral implications of bribery, conflict of interest, protection of investors and consumers, worker's rights, ethical leadership, and corporate philanthropy.[99]

Professional ethics is a closely related field that studies ethical principles applying to members of a specific profession, like engineers, medical doctors, lawyers, and teachers. It is a diverse field since different professions often have different responsibilities.[101] Principles applying to many professions include that the professional has the required expertise for the intended work and that they have personal integrity and are trustworthy. Further principles are to serve the interest of their target group, follow client confidentiality, and respect and uphold the client's rights, such as informed consent.[102] More precise requirements often vary between professions. A cornerstone of engineering ethics is to protect the public's safety, health, and well-being.[103] Legal ethics emphasizes the importance of respect for justice, personal integrity, and confidentiality.[104] Key factors in journalism ethics include accuracy, truthfulness, independence, and impartiality as well as proper attribution to avoid plagiarism.[105]

Others[edit]

Many other fields of applied ethics are discussed in the academic literature. Communication ethics covers moral principles in relation to communicative conduct. Two key issues in it are freedom of speech and speech responsibility. Freedom of speech concerns the ability to articulate one's opinions and ideas without the threats of punishment and censorship. Speech responsibility is about being accountable for the consequences of communicative action and inaction.[106] A closely related field is information ethics, which focuses on the moral implications of creating, controlling, disseminating, and using information.[107]

Nuclear ethics address the moral implications of nuclear technology, such as atom bombs.

The ethics of technology has implications for both communication ethics and information ethics in regard to communication and information technologies. In its widest sense, it examines the moral issues associated with any artifacts created and used for instrumental means, from simple artifacts like spears to high-tech computers and nanotechnology.[108] Central topics in the ethics of technology include the risks associated with creating new technologies, their responsible use, and questions surrounding the issue of human enhancement through technological means, such as prosthetic limbs, performance-enhancing drugs, and genetic enhancement.[109] Important subfields include computer ethics, ethics of artificial intelligence, machine ethics, ethics of nanotechnology, and nuclear ethics.[110]

The ethics of war investigates moral problems in relation to war and violent conflicts. According to just war theory, waging war is morally justified if it fulfills certain conditions. They are commonly divided into requirements concerning the cause to initiate violent activities, such as self-defense, and the way those violent activities are conducted, such as avoiding excessive harm to civilians in the pursuit of legitimate military targets.[111] Military ethics is a closely related field that is interested in the conduct of military personnel. It governs questions of the circumstances under which they are permitted to kill enemies, destroy infrastructure, and put the lives of their own troops at risk.[112] Additional topics are recruitment, training, and discharge of military personnel as well as the procurement of military equipment.[113]

Further fields of applied ethics include political ethics, which examines the moral dimensions of political decisions,[114] educational ethics, which covers ethical issues related to proper teaching practices,[115] and sexual ethics, which addresses the moral implications of sexual behavior.[116]

Metaethics[edit]

Main article: Metaethics

Metaethics is the branch of ethics that examines the nature, foundations, and scope of moral judgments, concepts, and values. It is not interested in what actions are right or wrong but in what it means for an action to be right or wrong and whether moral judgments are objective and can be true at all. It further examines the meaning of morality and moral terms.[117] Metaethics is a metatheory that operates on a higher level of abstraction than normative ethics by investigating its underlying background assumptions. Metaethical theories usually do not directly take substantive positions regarding normative ethical theories but they can influence them nonetheless by questioning the foundational principles on which they rest.[118]

Metaethics overlaps with various branches of philosophy. On the level of ontology, it is concerned with the metaphysical status of moral values and principles.[119] In relation to semantics, it asks what the meaning of moral terms is and whether moral statements have a truth value.[120] The epistemological side of metaethics discusses whether and how people can acquire moral knowledge.[121] Metaethics further covers psychological and anthropological considerations in regard to how moral judgments motivate people to act and how to explain cross-cultural differences in moral assessments.[122]

Basic concepts[edit]

Metaethics examines basic ethical concepts and their relations. Ethics is concerned with normative statements about what ought to be the case, in contrast to descriptive statements, which are about what is the case.[123] Duties and obligations express requirements of what people ought to do.[124] Duties are sometimes defined as counterparts of the rights that always accompany them. According to this view, someone has a duty to benefit another person if this other person has the right to receive that benefit.[125] Obligation and permission are contrasting terms that can be defined through each other: to be obligated to do something means that one is not permitted not to do it and to be permitted to do something means that one is not obligated not to do it.[126][c] Some theorists define obligations in terms of values, such as the good. When used in a general sense, good contrasts with bad. In relation to people and their intentions, the term evil rather than bad is often employed.[127]

Obligations are used to assess the moral status of actions, motives, and character traits.[128] An action is morally right if it is in tune with the obligations and morally wrong if it violates the obligations.[129] Supererogation is a special moral status that applies to cases in which the agent does more than is morally required of them.[130] To be morally responsible for an action usually means that the person possessed and exercised certain capacities or some form of control. People who are morally responsible deserve evaluative attitudes from others, such as praise or blame.[131]

Realism, relativism, and nihilism[edit]

A key debate in metaethics concerns the ontological status of morality and encompasses the question of whether ethical values and principles form part of reality. It examines whether moral properties exist as objective features independent of the human mind and culture rather than as subjective constructs or expressions of personal preferences and cultural norms.[132]

Moral realists accept the claim that there are objective moral facts. This view implies that moral values are mind-independent aspects of reality and that there is an absolute fact about whether a given action is right or wrong. A consequence of this view is that moral requirements have the same ontological status as non-moral facts: it is an objective fact whether there is an obligation to keep a promise just as there is an objective fact whether a thing has a black color.[132] Moral realism is often associated with the claim that there are universal ethical principles that apply equally to everyone.[133] It implies that if two people disagree about a moral evaluation then at least one of them is wrong. This observation is sometimes taken as an argument against moral realism since moral disagreement is widespread and concerns most fields.[134]

Moral relativists reject the idea that morality is an objective feature of reality. They argue instead that moral principles are human inventions. This means that a behavior is not objectively right or wrong but only subjectively right or wrong relative to a certain standpoint. Moral standpoints may differ between persons, cultures, and historical periods.[135] For example, moral statements like "slavery is wrong" or "suicide is permitted" may be true in one culture and false in another.[136] This position can be understood in analogy to Einstein's theory of relativity, which states that the magnitude of physical properties like mass, length, and duration depends on the frame of reference of the observer.[137] Some moral relativists hold that moral systems are constructed to serve certain goals such as social coordination. According to this view, different societies and different social groups within a society construct different moral systems based on their diverging purposes.[138] A different explanation states that morality arises from moral emotions, which people project onto the external world.[139]

Moral nihilists deny the existence of moral facts. They are opposed to both objective moral facts defended by moral realism and subjective moral facts defended by moral relativism. They believe that the basic assumptions underlying moral claims are misguided. Some moral nihilists, like Friedrich Nietzsche, conclude from this that anything is allowed. A slightly different view emphasizes that moral nihilism is not itself a moral position about what is allowed and prohibited but the rejection of any moral position.[140] Moral nihilism agrees with moral relativism that there are different standpoints according to which people judge actions to be right or wrong. However, it disagrees that this practice involves a form of morality and understands it instead as one among many types of human practices.[141]

Naturalism and non-naturalism[edit]

Main articles: Naturalism and Non-naturalism

An influential debate among moral realists is between naturalism and non-naturalism. Naturalism states that moral properties are natural properties and are in this respect similar to the natural properties accessible to empirical observation and investigated by the natural sciences, like color and shape.[142] Some moral naturalists hold that moral properties are a unique and basic type of natural property. Another view states that moral properties are real but not a fundamental part of reality and can be reduced to other natural properties, for example, concerning what causes pleasure and pain.[143]

Non-naturalism accepts that moral properties form part of reality and argues that moral features are not identical or reducible to natural properties. This view is usually motivated by the idea that moral properties are unique because they express normative features or what should be the case.[144] Proponents of this position often emphasize this uniqueness by claiming that it is a fallacy to define ethics in terms of natural entities or to infer prescriptive from descriptive statements.[145]

Cognitivism and non-cognitivism[edit]

Main articles: Cognitivism and Non-cognitivism

The metaethical debate between cognitivism and non-cognitivism belongs to the field of semantics and concerns the meaning of moral statements. According to cognitivism, moral statements like "Abortion is morally wrong" and "Going to war is never morally justified" are truth-apt. This means that they all have a truth value: they are either true or false. Cognitivism only claims that moral statements have a truth value but is not interested in which truth value they have. It is often seen as the default position since moral statements resemble other statements, like "Abortion is a medical procedure" or "Going to war is a political decision", which have a truth value.[146]

The semantic position of cognitivism is closely related to the ontological position of moral realism and philosophers who accept one often accept the other as well. An exception is J. L. Mackie's error theory, which combines cognitivism with moral nihilism by claiming that all moral statements are false because there are no moral facts.[147]

Non-cognitivism is the view that moral statements lack a truth value. According to this view, the statement "Murder is wrong" is neither true nor false. Some non-cognitivists claim that moral statements have no meaning at all. A different interpretation is that they express other types of meaning contents. Emotivism holds that they articulate emotional attitudes. According to this view, the statement "Murder is wrong" expresses that the speaker has negative moral attitudes towards murder or dislikes it. Prescriptivism, by contrast, understands moral statements as commands. According to this view, stating that "Murder is wrong" expresses a command like "Do not commit murder".[148]

Moral knowledge[edit]

The epistemology of ethics studies whether or how one can know moral truths. Foundationalist views state that some moral beliefs are basic and do not require further justification. Ethical intuitionism is one foundationalist view that states that humans have a special cognitive faculty through which they can know right from wrong. Intuitionists often argue that general moral truths, like "lying is wrong", are self-evident and that it is possible to know them a priori without relying on empirical experience. A different foundationalist view relies not on general intuitions but on particular observations. It holds that if people are confronted with a concrete moral situation, they can perceive whether right or wrong conduct was involved.[149]

In contrast to foundationalists, coherentists hold that there are no basic moral beliefs. They argue that beliefs form a complex network and mutually support and justify one another. According to this view, a moral belief can only amount to knowledge if it coheres with the rest of the beliefs in the network.[149] Moral skeptics reject the idea that moral knowledge is possible by arguing that people are unable to distinguish between right and wrong behavior. Moral skepticism is often criticized based on the claim that it leads to immoral behavior.[150]

The trolley problem is a thought experiment about the moral difference between doing and allowing harm.

Thought experiments are a common methodological device in ethics to decide between competing theories. They usually present an imagined situation involving an ethical dilemma and explore how moral intuitions about what behavior is right depend on particular factors in the imagined situation.[151] For example, in the trolley problem, a person can flip a switch to redirect a trolley from one track to another, thereby sacrificing the life of one person in order to save five. This scenario explores how the difference between doing and allowing harm affects moral obligations.[152] Another thought experiment examines the moral implications of abortion by imagining a situation in which a person gets connected without their consent to an ill violinist. It explores whether it would be morally permissible to sever the connection within the next nine months even if this would lead to the violinist's death.[153]

Moral motivation[edit]

On the level of psychology, metaethics is interested in how moral beliefs and experiences affect behavior. According to motivational internalists, there is a direct link between moral judgments and action. This means that every judgment about what is right motivates the person to act accordingly. For example, Socrates defends a strong form of motivational internalism by holding that a person can only perform an evil deed if they are unaware that it is evil. Weaker forms of motivational internalism allow that people can act against moral judgments, for example, because of weakness of the will. Motivational externalists accept that people can judge a behavior to be morally required without feeling a reason to engage in it. This means that moral judgments do not always provide motivational force. The debate between internalism and externalism is relevant for explaining the behavior of psychopaths or sociopaths, who fail either to judge that a behavior is wrong or to translate their judgment into action.[154] A closely related question is whether moral judgments can provide motivation on their own or need to be accompanied by other mental states, such as a desire to act morally.[155]

Related fields[edit]

Value theory[edit]

Main articles: Value theory and Axiology

Value theory, also referred to as axiology,[d] is the philosophical study of value. It aims to understand what value is and what types of value there are. Further questions include what kinds of things have value and how valuable they are.[157] A central distinction is between intrinsic and instrumental value. An entity has intrinsic value if it is good in itself or good for its own sake. An entity has instrumental value if it is valuable as a means to something else, for example, by causing something that has intrinsic value.[158] Another key topic is about what entities have intrinsic value, for example, whether pleasure has intrinsic value and whether there are other sources of intrinsic value besides pleasure.[159]

There are disagreements about the exact relation between value theory and ethics. Some philosophers characterize value theory as a subdiscipline of ethics while others see value theory as the broader term that encompasses other fields besides ethics, such as aesthetics and political philosophy.[160] A different characterization sees the two disciplines as overlapping but distinct fields.[161] The term axiological ethics is sometimes used for the discipline studying this overlap, i.e., for the part of ethics that studies values.[162] The two disciplines are sometimes distinguished based on their focus: ethics is about moral behavior or what is right while value theory is about value or what is good.[163] Some ethical theories, like consequentialism, stand very close to value theory by defining what is right in terms of what is good. But this is not true for ethics in general and deontological theories tend to reject the idea that what is good can be used to define what is right.[164]

Moral psychology[edit]

Main article: Moral psychology

Moral psychology explores the psychological foundations and processes involved in moral behavior. It is an empirical science that studies how humans think and act in moral contexts. It is interested in how moral reasoning and judgments take place, how moral character forms, what sensitivity people have to moral evaluations, and how people attribute and react to moral responsibility.[165]

One of its key topics is moral development or the question of how morality develops on a psychological level from infancy to adulthood.[166] According to Lawrence Kohlberg, for example, children go through different stages of moral development as they understand moral principles first as fixed rules governing reward and punishment, then as conventional social norms, and later as abstract principles of what is objectively right across societies.[167] A closely related question is whether and how people can be taught to act morally.[168]

Evolutionary ethics is a subfield of moral psychology and sociobiology. It explores how evolutionary processes have shaped ethics. One of its key ideas is that natural selection is responsible for moral behavior and moral sensitivity. It interprets morality as an adaptation to evolutionary pressure that augments fitness by offering a selective advantage.[169] Altruism, for example, can provide benefits to group survival by improving cooperation.[170]

Descriptive ethics[edit]

Main article: Descriptive ethics

Descriptive ethics, also called comparative ethics,[171] studies actually existing moral codes, practices, and beliefs. It investigates and compares moral phenomena in different societies and different groups within a society. It aims to provide a value-neutral and empirical description without judging or justifying which practices are objectively right. For instance, the question of how nurses think about the ethical implications of abortion belongs to descriptive ethics. Another example is descriptive business ethics, which describes ethical standards in the context of business, including common practices, official policies, and employee opinions. Descriptive ethics also has a historical dimension by exploring how moral practices and beliefs have changed over time.[172]

Descriptive ethics is a multidisciplinary field that is covered by disciplines such as anthropology, sociology, psychology, and history. Its empirical outlook contrasts with the philosophical inquiry into normative questions, such as which ethical principles are correct and how to justify them.[173]

History[edit]

Main article: History of ethics

According to Laozi's teachings of Daoism, humans should aim to live in harmony with the natural order of the universe.

The history of ethics studies how moral philosophy has developed and evolved in the course of history.[174] It has its origin in the ancient civilizations. In ancient Egypt, the concept of Maat was used as an ethical principle to guide behavior and maintain order by emphasizing the importance of truth, balance, and harmony.[175] In ancient India, the Vedas and Upanishads were written as the foundational texts of Hindu philosophy and discussed the role of duty and the consequences of one's actions.[176] Buddhist ethics also originated in ancient India and advocated compassion, non-violence, and the pursuit of enlightenment.[177] Ancient China saw the emergence of Confucianism, which focuses on moral conduct and self-cultivation by acting in accordance with virtues, and Daoism, which teaches that human behavior should be in harmony with the natural order of the universe.[178]

In ancient Greece, Socrates emphasized the importance of inquiry into what a good life is by critically questioning established ideas and exploring concepts like virtue, justice, courage, and wisdom.[179] According to Plato, to lead a good life means that the different parts of the soul are in harmony with each other.[180] For Aristotle, a good life is associated with being happy by cultivating virtues and flourishing.[181] The close relation between right action and happiness was also explored by Hellenistic schools of Epicureanism, which recommended a simple lifestyle without indulging in sensory pleasures, and Stoicism, which advocated living in tune with reason and virtue while practicing self-mastery and becoming immune to disturbing emotions.[182]

Ethical thought in the medieval period was strongly influenced by religious teachings. Christian philosophers interpreted moral principles as divine commands originating from God.[183] Thomas Aquinas developed natural law ethics by claiming that ethical behavior consists in following the laws and order of nature, which he believed were created by God.[184] In the Islamic world, philosophers like Al-Farabi and Avicenna synthesized ancient Greek philosophy with the ethical teachings of Islam while emphasizing the harmony between reason and faith.[185] In medieval India, philosophers like Adi Shankara and Ramanuja saw the practice of spirituality to attain liberation as the highest goal of human behavior.[186]

G. E. Moore's book Principia Ethica was partly responsible for the emergence of metaethics in the 20th century.

Moral philosophy in the modern period was characterized by a shift toward a secular approach to ethics. Thomas Hobbes identified self-interest as the primary drive of humans. He concluded that it would lead to "a war of every man against every man" unless a social contract is established to avoid this outcome.[187] David Hume thought that only moral sentiments, like empathy, can motivate ethical actions while he saw reason not as a motivating factor but only as what anticipates the consequences of possible actions.[188] Immanuel Kant, by contrast, saw reason as the source of morality. He formulated a deontological theory, according to which the ethical value of actions depends on their conformity with moral laws independent of their outcome. These laws take the form of categorical imperatives, which are universal requirements that apply to every situation.[189] Another influential development in this period was the formulation of utilitarianism by Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill. According to the utilitarian doctrine, actions should promote happiness while reducing suffering and the right action is the one that produces the greatest good for the greatest number of people.[190]

An important development in 20th-century ethics in analytic philosophy was the emergence of metaethics.[191] Significant early contributions to this field were made by G. E. Moore, who argued that moral values are essentially different from other properties found in the natural world.[192] R. M. Hare followed this idea in formulating his prescriptivism, which states that moral statements are commands that, unlike regular judgments, are neither true nor false.[193] An influential argument for moral realism was made by Derek Parfit, who argued that morality concerns objective features of reality that give people reasons to act in one way or another.[194] Bernard Williams agreed with the close relation between reasons and ethics but defended a subjective view instead that sees reasons as internal mental states that may or may not reflect external reality.[195] Another development in this period was the revival of ancient virtue ethics by philosophers like Philippa Foot.[196] In the field of political philosophy, John Rawls relied on Kantian ethics to analyze social justice as a form of fairness.[197] In continental philosophy, phenomenologists such as Max Scheler and Nicolai Hartmann built ethical systems based on the claim that values have objective reality that can be investigated using the phenomenological method.[198] Existentialists like Jean-Paul Sartre, by contrast, held that values are created by humans and explored the consequences of this view in relation to individual freedom, responsibility, and authenticity.[199] This period also saw the emergence of feminist ethics, which questions traditional ethical assumptions associated with a male perspective and puts alternative concepts, like care, at the center.[200]

See also[edit]

Effective altruism

Ethical movement

Index of ethics articles

Longtermism

Master of Applied Ethics

Neuroethics

Outline of ethics

Practical philosophy

Science of morality

Trail ethics

References[edit]

Notes[edit]

^ Some theorists define teleological ethics as the wider term that also encompasses certain forms of virtue ethics.[20]

^ Some ethicists state that contractualism is not a normative ethical theory but a metaethical theory because of its emphasis on how moral norms are justified.[56]

^ Deontic logic provides a formal system describing the logical relations between these and similar concepts.[126]

^ There are disagreements in the academic literature about whether they are synonyms or whether one or the other is the wider term.[156]

Citations[edit]

^ McNamara & Van De Putte 2022, Lead Section, § 1.2 The Traditional Scheme and the Modal AnalogiesRibino & Lodato 2019, p. 3

^ Vogt 2017, pp. 42–43Hollenbach 2002, p. 3

^ Norman 2005, p. 622Nagel 2006, Lead SectionCrisp 2011, § 1. Ethics and MetaethicsDeigh 1999, pp. 284–285Mulvaney 2009, pp. vii–xi

^ Nagel 2006, § What Is Morality?Crisp 2011, § 1. Ethics and MetaethicsHaiming 2021, pp. 1–2Paul & Elder 2005, § Why a Mini-Guide on Ethical Reasoning?

^ AHD staff 2022Crisp 2011, § 1. Ethics and MetaethicsDeigh 1999, pp. 284–285

^ Athanassoulis 2012, pp. 22–27Downie 2005, p. 271Blum 2006

^ Crisp 2011, § 1. Ethics and MetaethicsNagel 2006, Lead SectionDittmer, § 1. Applied Ethics as Distinct from Normative Ethics and Metaethic

^ Hoad 1993, p. 156Liddell & Scott 1889, p. 349

^ Dittmer, § 1. Applied Ethics as Distinct from Normative Ethics and MetaethicsKagan 1998, pp. 1–2Gustafson 2020, pp. 1–2Thomas 2022

^ Kagan 1998, pp. 1–3

^ Barsh & Lisewski 2013, p. 29Kagan 1998, pp. 18–19

^ Sims 2017, p. 6Barsh & Lisewski 2013, p. 29Kagan 1998, pp. 7–10Sulmasy & Sugarman 2010, p. 11Pera & Tonder 2005, p. 7

^ Kagan 1998, p. 3Dittmer, § 1. Applied Ethics as Distinct from Normative Ethics and Metaethics

^ Kagan 1998, p. 2Gustafsson & Pietarinen 2016, pp. 125–126

^ Kagan 1998, pp. 2–3

^ Thomas 2022Dittmer, § 1. Applied Ethics as Distinct from Normative Ethics and MetaethicsKagan 1998, pp. 2, 11

^ Crisp 2005, pp. 200–201

^ Hursthouse & Pettigrove 2023, Lead SectionKagan 1998, p. 11

^ Bunnin & Yu 2009, p. 134

^ McNaughton & Rawling 1998, § 1. Act-consequentialism

^ Sinnott-Armstrong 2023, Lead SectionHaines, Lead SectionHooker 2023, § 1. Utilitarianism

^ a b Crisp 2005, pp. 200–201Alexander & Moore 2021, § 1. Deontology’s Foil: Consequentialism

^ Dorsey 2020, pp. 97–98

^ Sinnott-Armstrong 2023, Lead SectionHaines, Lead Section

^ Hooker 2005, pp. 162–164Zimmerman 2015, p. 17

^ Hooker 2005, pp. 162–164Edmundson 2004, p. 158Brink 2020, p. 382

^ Sinnott-Armstrong 2023, Lead Section

^ Sinnott-Armstrong 2023, Lead Section, § 5. Consequences of What? Rights, Relativity, and RulesHooker 2005, pp. 162–164

^ Haines, Lead SectionSinnott-Armstrong 2023, Lead Section, § 3. What Is Good? Hedonistic Vs. Pluralistic ConsequentialismsAlexander & Moore 2021, § 1. Deontology’s Foil: ConsequentialismHooker 2005, pp. 162–164

^ a b Alexander & Moore 2021, § 1. Deontology’s Foil: Consequentialism

^ Hooker 2005, pp. 162–164Alexander & Moore 2021, § 1. Deontology’s Foil: Consequentialism

^ Hooker 2005, pp. 162–164Cummiskey 1996, pp. 157–158

^ Sinnott-Armstrong 2023, 5. Consequences of What? Rights, Relativity, and RulesHooker 2023, Lead SectionHaines, § 1f. Rule ConsequentialismHooker 2005, p. 164Alexander & Moore 2021, § 1. Deontology’s Foil: Consequentialism

^ Hooker 2005, pp. 162–164Sinnott-Armstrong 2023, § 1. Classic Utilitarianism, § 4. Which Consequences? Actual Vs. Expected Consequentialisms

^ Hooker 2005, p. 164Slote 2005, pp. 938–939Alexander & Moore 2021, § 1. Deontology’s Foil: ConsequentialismSinger 2016, 47–48Byron 2004, p. 9

^ Littlejohn, § 1c. Mozi (c. 470-391 B.C.E.) and MohismZhang 2023, p. 96

^ Slote 2005, pp. 936, 938Sinnott-Armstrong 2023, § 1. Classic Utilitarianism

^ Moore 2019, Lead Section, § 2. Ethical Hedonism

^ Slote 2005, pp. 936, 938Morales 2005, p. 141Kivy 2011, p. 238

^ Slote 2005, p. 938Hooker 2014, p. 281

^ Crisp 2005, pp. 200–201Alexander & Moore 2021, § 2. Deontological Theories

^ Simpson, § 6c. Deontological Pluralism and Prima Facie DutiesCrisp 2005, pp. 200–201

^ Crisp 2005, pp. 200–201Simpson, § 6c. Deontological Pluralism and Prima Facie Duties

^ Alexander & Moore 2021, § 2. Deontological TheoriesCrisp 2005, pp. 200–201

^ Alexander & Moore 2021, § 2. Deontological TheoriesHale 2017, p. 216Kumm & Walen 2014, p. 81

^ Alexander & Moore 2021, § 2. Deontological Theories

^ Alexander & Moore 2021, § 2.4 Deontological Theories and Kant

^ Johnson & Cureton 2022, Lead SectionO'Neill, § 1. Kant’s EthicsJankowiak, § 5. Moral Theory

^ Johnson & Cureton 2022, Lead Section

^ O'Neill, § 1. Kant’s EthicsJankowiak, § 5. Moral Theory

^ Jankowiak, § 5. Moral TheoryJohnson & Cureton 2022, § 2. Good Will, Moral Worth and Duty, § 3. Duty and Respect for Moral Law

^ Austin, Lead SectionMurphy 2019, Lead Section

^ Brown 2004, p. 13Flynn 2012, p. 167

^ Flynn 2012, p. 167Myers & Noebel 2015, p. 241

^ Alexander & Moore 2021, § 2.3 Contractualist Deontological TheoriesSullivan 2001, p. 118Ashford & Mulgan 2018, Lead Section

^ Alexander & Moore 2021, § 2.3 Contractualist Deontological Theories

^ Chakraborti 2023, p. 39Metselaar & Widdershoven 2016, pp. 895–896Finlayson & Rees 2023, § 3.3 The Principles of Discourse Ethics and Their Justification

^ Slote 2005a, pp. 947–948Hursthouse & Pettigrove 2023, Lead Section

^ Hursthouse & Pettigrove 2023, Lead Section, § 1.1 VirtueSlote 2005a, pp. 947–948

^ Hursthouse & Pettigrove 2023, § 1.2 Practical WisdomCaro, Marraffa & Vaccarezza 2021, pp. 31–33

^ a b Hursthouse & Pettigrove 2023, § 2. Forms of Virtue EthicsNafsika Athanassoulis, § 3. Virtue Ethical Theories

^ Nafsika Athanassoulis, § 3c. The Ethics of CareSander-Staudt, Lead Section

^ Oosthuizen 2002, p. 21Kraut 2022, Lead Section, § 5. The Doctrine of the Mean

^ Stephens, Lead SectionCampbell 1985, pp. 327–328

^ Hursthouse 1999, p. 3

^ Peterson 2020, pp. 65–66Legg & Hookway 2021, § 6.2 EthicsLaFollette 2007, § The Primacy of Habits, § Morality Is a Habit

^ Bauman 1993, pp. 8–13Kendall 2017, pp. 195–196

^ Shaver 2023, Lead Section, § 2. Ethical EgoismMcEwan 2001, p. 87

^ Bollag 2006, pp. 15–16Blidstein 1995, pp. 5–6

^ Beach 1988, p. 36Porter 2010, p. 73

^ Verhoeven 2013, p. 27

^ Chowdhury 2019, p. 494

^ Beaman & Strumos 2022, p. 76

^ Chakraborti 2023, p. 122

^ Wu & Wokutch 2008, p. 404

^ Ames 2013, p. 1681Brannigan 2010, p. 145

^ Darwall 2003, p. 17Chakraborti 2023, pp. 619–620

^ Almond 1998, Lead Section, § 1. DefinitionsDittmer, Lead Section, § 1. Applied Ethics as Distinct from Normative Ethics and MetaethicsPetersen & Ryberg 2022Winkler 1998, pp. 174–175

^ Winkler 1998, pp. 175–176

^ Beaucham 2003, pp. 7–9

^ Beaucham 2003, pp. 7–9Winkler 1998, pp. 176–117Almond 1998, § 2. Theory and Practice

^ Almond 1998, § 2. Theory and Practice

^ Almond 1998, § 1. Definitions

^ Ryberg 2010, p. 3Meynell & Paron 2023, p. 11Chakraborti 2023, p. 620Winkler 1998, pp. 174–175

^ Dittmer, § 3. BioethicsGordon, Lead SectionGillon 1998, pp. 267–268

^ Gordon, Lead Section, § 4. The Idea of Moral Status in BioethicsDittmer, § 4a. Theories of Moral Standing and Personhood

^ Holmes 2018, pp. 288–289Gordon, § 3d. Environmental Ethics

^ Dittmer, § 3. BioethicsGordon, Lead Section, § 1. Preliminary Distinctions

^ Gordon, Lead Section, § 3a. Introduction

^ a b Gordon, Lead Section, § 3b. Medical Ethics

^ Dittmer, § 3. BioethicsGordon, Lead Section, § 3b. Medical Ethics

^ Dittmer, § 3. BioethicsDelden 1998, pp. 200–201

^ Wilson, Lead SectionGordon, Lead Section, § 3c. Animal EthicsHolmes 2018, pp. 317–319

^ Holmes 2018, pp. 333–334

^ Francione 2004, pp. 115–116Yount 2007, p. 26

^ Gordon, § 3d. Environmental EthicsSandler 1998, pp. 105–106Brennan & Lo 2022, Lead Section

^ Brennan & Lo 2022, § 1. Introduction: The Challenge of Environmental EthicsGordon, § 3d. Environmental Ethics

^ Gordon, § 3d. Environmental EthicsCochrane, § 2. Radical EcologySmith 2018, p. 36

^ a b Rendtorff 1998, pp. 365–366Dittmer, § 2. Business Ethics

^ Dueñas et al. 2018, pp. xv–xviDittmer, § 2. Business EthicsRendtorff 1998, pp. 365–366

^ Airaksinen 1998Dittmer, § 5. Professional Ethics

^ Airaksinen 1998, pp. 617–620

^ Catalano 2022, p. 17

^ Parker & Evans 2007, pp. 22–23

^ Medvecky & Leach 2019, p. 35Mentan 2022, p. 280Patching & Hirst 2013, p. 69

^ Kvalnes 2023, pp. 101, 105Christians 2005

^ ten Have & Patrão Neves 2021, p. 633Elrod & Smith 2005

^ Braunack-Mayer, Street & Palmer 1998, pp. 321–322

^ Braunack-Mayer, Street & Palmer 1998, pp. 323–326Robson & Tsou 2023, pp. 16–17

^ Tzafestas 2015, p. 2Mitcham 2022, p. 101

^ Frowe 2021, Lead SectionLazar 2020, Lead Section, § 3. Jus Ad Bellum, § 4. Jus in BelloSorabji & Rodin 2007, pp. 2–3

^ Wolfendale 2007, pp. 47–78Baumann 2007, pp. 34–35

^ Fotion 1998, pp. 121, 123–124, 126

^ Hall & Sabl 2022, pp. 1–2Gay 2006, p. 189

^ Maxwell 2023, pp. 609–610

^ Boonin 2022, p. 1

^ Harrison 2005, pp. 588–589DeLapp, Lead SectionSayre-McCord 2023, Lead Section

^ DeLapp, Lead Section, § 2. The Normative Relevance of MetaethicsSayre-McCord 2023, Lead Section, § 1. General Observations

^ DeLapp, Lead Section, § 4. Ontological Issues in MetaethicsSayre-McCord 2023, Lead Section, § 3. Naturalism and Non-naturalism

^ DeLapp, Lead Section, § 3. Semantic Issues in MetaethicsSayre-McCord 2023, Lead Section, § 4. Is/Ought and the Open Question Argument

^ DeLapp, Lead Section, § 6. Epistemological Issues in MetaethicsSayre-McCord 2023, Lead Section, § 5. Moral Epistemology

^ DeLapp, Lead Section, § 5. Psychology and Metaethics, 7. Anthropological ConsiderationsSayre-McCord 2023, Lead Section, § 6. Morals, Motives, and Reasons, § 7. Freedom and Responsibility

^ Miller 2023, pp. 1–4Lloyd & Hansen 2003, p. 21

^ O'Neill 2013, pp. 423–424

^ Stoljar 1984, pp. 36–37Feibleman 1967, pp. 121–122Corbin 1924, pp. 501–502

^ a b McNamara & Van De Putte 2022, § 1.2 The Traditional Scheme and the Modal AnalogiesBelzer, § 1. Standard Deontic Logic (SDL)

^ Haiming 2021, pp. 75–76Miller 2023, pp. 4–5Calder 2022, Lead Section

^ Miller 2023, pp. 4–5

^ Pick 2004, pp. 159–160Haiming 2021, pp. 88–89Miller 2023, pp. 5–6

^ Heyd 2019, Lead SectionMiller 2023, pp. 5–6

^ Talbert 2019, Lead SectionWilliams, Lead Section, § 1. Introduction

^ a b DeLapp, Lead Section, § 4a. Moral RealismsSayre-McCord 2023a, Lead Section

^ DeLapp, § 4a. Moral Realisms

^ Sayre-McCord 2023a, § 1. Moral DisagreementDeLapp, § 4a. Moral Realisms

^ DeLapp, § 4b. Moral RelativismsGowans 2021, Lead Section, § 2. Forms and ArgumentsWestacott, Lead SectionDreier 2007, pp. 240–241

^ Westacott, § 2g. Moral RelativismGowans 2021, § 6. Metaethical Moral Relativism

^ Dreier 2007, pp. 240–241

^ DeLapp, § 4b. Moral RelativismsGowans 2021, § 6. Metaethical Moral Relativism

^ Dreier 2007, p. 241

^ Dreier 2007, pp. 240–241Krellenstein 2017, pp. 75–90

^ Dreier 2007, pp. 241–242

^ Lutz 2023, Lead Section, § 1. What Is Moral Naturalism?DeLapp, § 4a. Moral Realisms

^ Lutz 2023, § 1. What Is Moral Naturalism?, § 2. Descriptivism and ReductivismDeLapp, § 4a. Moral Realisms

^ FitzPatrick 2011, pp. 7–35, Ethical Non-Naturalism and Normative PropertiesRidge 2019, Lead Section

^ Ridge 2019, § 1. The Naturalistic FallacyShafer-Landau 2020, p. 148

^ DeLapp, § 3a. Cognitivism Versus Non-CognitivismMiller 2023, pp. 14–15

^ Miller 2023, pp. 14–15

^ Miller 2023, pp. 14–15DeLapp, § 3a. Cognitivism Versus Non-CognitivismMoreland & Craig 2017, p. 417

^ a b DeLapp, § 6. Epistemological Issues in MetaethicsSayre-McCord 2023, § 5. Moral Epistemology

^ Sinnott-Armstrong 2019, Lead Section, § 1. Varieties of Moral Skepticism, § 2. A Presumption Against Moral Skepticism?Sayre-McCord 2023, § 5. Moral Epistemology

^ Brun 2017, pp. 195–196Brown & Fehige 2019, Lead SectionBaggini & Fosl 2024, p. 284

^ Brun 2017, p. 195Woollard & Howard-Snyder 2022, § 3. The Trolley Problem and the Doing/Allowing DistinctionRini, § 8. Moral Cognition and Moral Epistemology

^ Brun 2017, p. 195Brown & Fehige 2019, § 1. Important Characteristics of Thought Experiments

^ DeLapp, § 5. Psychology and MetaethicsSayre-McCord 2023, § 6. Morals, Motives, and ReasonsRosati 2016, Lead Section, § 3. Moral Judgment and MotivationReilly 1977, pp. 101–102Milevski 2017, p. 3

^ Rosati 2016, Lead Section, § 3. Moral Judgment and Motivation

^ Schroeder 2021, Lead SectionHirose & Olson 2015, pp. 1–2Grenz, Guretzki & Nordling 2010, p. 18

^ Smith & Thomas, Lead SectionSchroeder 2021, Lead SectionHirose & Olson 2015, pp. 1–2

^ Schroeder 2021, § 2.1 Intrinsic ValueZimmerman & Bradley 2019, Lead Section

^ Schroeder 2021, § 2.2 Monism/PluralismZimmerman & Bradley 2019, § 1. What Has Intrinsic Value?

^ Schroeder 2021, Lead SectionCowan 2020, pp. 17–18Stecker 2010, pp. 525–526

^ Hirose & Olson 2015, pp. 1–2

^ Kupperman 2005, pp. 73–74

^ Calida 2022, pp. 77–79Grenz, Guretzki & Nordling 2010, p. 18

^ Crisp 2005, pp. 200–201Alexander & Moore 2021, § 1. Deontology’s Foil: ConsequentialismSchroeder 2021, § 3. Relation to the Deontic

^ Doris et al. 2020, Lead Section, § Introduction: What Is Moral Psychology?Thoma 2015, pp. 230–231Rudy-Hiller 2022, p. 509

^ Puka, Lead Section, § 1. What It Is

^ Linn 1994, p. 330Eysenck 2004, pp. 586–588

^ Meyer 2023, Abstract, Lead SectionMatsuba, Murzyn & Hart 2011, pp. 181–182

^ Schroeder, Lead SectionMesoudi & Danielson 2008, pp. 229–230Rice 2009, p. 153

^ Rice 2009, p. 153Post 2011, p. 118

^ Monzon 2012, p. 208

^ Sims 2017, p. 6Barsh & Lisewski 2013, p. 29Sulmasy & Sugarman 2010, p. 11Pera & Tonder 2005, p. 7Kagan 1998, pp. 7–10

^ Sulmasy & Sugarman 2010, p. 11Pera & Tonder 2005, p. 7Funk 2021, p. 175

^ Abelson & Nielsen 2006, p. 394Norman 2005, p. 622

^ Brandon 1975, The Idea of the Judgment of the Dead in Ancient Near EastOrtiz 2020, PrefaceKarenga 2004, pp. 175–176

^ Perrett 2016, Indian Philosophy: A Brief Historical Overview, The Ancient Period of Indian PhilosophyTebbit 2013, p. 400

^ Thapar 1978, p. 48Grayling 2019, Indian Philosophy

^ Littlejohn, § 1b. Confucius (551-479 B.C.E.) of the Analects, § 1e. The DaodejingBoyd & Timpe 2021, p. 64Slingerland 2007, p. 77

^ Norman 2005, p. 623Abelson & Nielsen 2006, pp. 394–396, 398

^ Norman 2005, p. 623Abelson & Nielsen 2006, pp. 396–398

^ Norman 2005, p. 623Abelson & Nielsen 2006, pp. 397–398

^ Norman 2005, p. 623Abelson & Nielsen 2006, pp. 399–400

^ Norman 2005, p. 623Abelson & Nielsen 2006, p. 401

^ Norman 2005, p. 623Abelson & Nielsen 2006, pp. 403–404

^ Mattila 2022, p. 2Sajoo 2008, p. 60

^ Dalal 2021, Lead SectionRanganathan, Lead Section, § 4b. Rāmānuja’s SoteriologyGrayling 2019, Indian Philosophy

^ Norman 2005, p. 624Abelson & Nielsen 2006, pp. 404–406

^ Norman 2005, p. 624Abelson & Nielsen 2006, pp. 408–409

^ Norman 2005, p. 625Abelson & Nielsen 2006, pp. 410–412

^ Norman 2005, pp. 624–625Abelson & Nielsen 2006, pp. 412–414

^ Norman 2005, p. 626

^ Norman 2005, p. 626Abelson & Nielsen 2006, pp. 418–419

^ Norman 2005, p. 626Abelson & Nielsen 2006, pp. 429–430

^ McDonald 2017, pp. 95–96Lazari-Radek & Singer 2017, pp. 282–283

^ Chappell & Smyth 2023, § 5. Internal and External ReasonsKriegel 1999, pp. 281–282

^ Norman 2005, p. 627

^ Das 2021, pp. 118–119Wenar 2021, § 4. Justice as Fairness: Justice Within a Liberal Society

^ Abelson & Nielsen 2006, pp. 421–422

^ Abelson & Nielsen 2006, pp. 426–428

^ Norlock 2019, Lead SectionImafidon 2015, p. 211

Sources[edit]

Abelson, Raziel; Nielsen, Kai (2006). "Ethics, History of". In Borchert, Donald M. (ed.). Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 3: Determinables–Fuzzy Logic (2. ed.). Thomson Gale, Macmillan Reference. ISBN 978-0-02-866072-1.

AHD staff (2022). "Ethics". The American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language. HarperCollins. Archived from the original on January 6, 2024. Retrieved January 6, 2024.

Airaksinen, T. (1998). "Professional Ethics". In Chadwick, Ruth (ed.). Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics (2 ed.). Academic Press. ISBN 978-0-12-373932-2.

Alexander, Larry; Moore, Michael (2021). "Deontological Ethics". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on June 20, 2023. Retrieved December 30, 2023.

Almond, Brenda (1998). "Applied Ethics". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-L005-1. ISBN 978-0-415-25069-6. Archived from the original on February 1, 2024. Retrieved December 23, 2023.

Ames, Roger T. (2013). "Taoist Ethics". In Becker, Lawrence C.; Becker, Charlotte B. (eds.). Encyclopedia of Ethics. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-135-35096-3. Archived from the original on January 1, 2024. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Ashford, Elizabeth; Mulgan, Tim (2018). "Contractualism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on November 9, 2020. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Athanassoulis, Nafsika (2012). Virtue Ethics. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-4411-6287-8. Archived from the original on January 6, 2024. Retrieved January 7, 2024.

Austin, Michael W. "Divine Command Theory". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on December 31, 2023. Retrieved December 31, 2023.

Baggini, Julian; Fosl, Peter S. (2024). The Ethics Toolkit: A Compendium of Ethical Concepts and Methods. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-119-89197-0. Archived from the original on February 1, 2024. Retrieved January 7, 2024.

Barsh, Adele; Lisewski, Amy (2013). "Library Managers and Ethical Leadership: A Survey of Current Practices from the Perspective of Business Ethics". In Besnoy, Amy (ed.). Ethics And Integrity In Libraries. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-99372-8. Archived from the original on December 28, 2023. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Bauman, Zygmunt (1993). Postmodern Ethics. Blackwell. ISBN 978-0-631-18693-9.

Baumann, Dieter (2007). "Military Ethics: A Task for Armies". Military Medicine. 172 (Supplement 2): 34–38. doi:10.7205/MILMED.173.Supplement_2.34. PMID 18214134.

Beach, Waldo (1988). Christian Ethics in the Protestant Tradition. Westminster John Knox Press. ISBN 978-0-8042-0793-5. Archived from the original on January 1, 2024. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Beaman, Lori G.; Strumos, Lauren (2022). "Smudging, Yoga, Ethical Veganism: Exploring the Boundaries of Religious and Spiritual Practice in Law". In Mossière, Géraldine (ed.). New Spiritualities and the Cultures of Well-being. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-3-031-06263-6. Archived from the original on January 1, 2024. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Beaucham, Tom L. (2003). "The Nature of Applied Ethics". In Frey, R. G.; Wellman, Christopher Heath (eds.). A Companion to Applied Ethics. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-4051-7190-8. Archived from the original on February 1, 2024. Retrieved December 27, 2023.

Belzer, Marvin. "Deontic Logic". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. Archived from the original on January 7, 2024. Retrieved January 7, 2024.

Blidstein, Gerald J. (1995). "Tikkun Olam". Tradition: A Journal of Orthodox Jewish Thought. 29 (2): 5–43. ISSN 0041-0608. JSTOR 23260803. Archived from the original on January 1, 2024. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Blum, Lawrence (2006). "Ethics and Morality". In Borchert, Donald (ed.). Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. ISBN 978-0-02-865790-5. Archived from the original on June 7, 2023. Retrieved January 7, 2024.

Bollag, David (2006). "Jewish Religious Law". In Hurwitz, Peter Joel; Picard, Jacques; Steinberg, Avraham (eds.). Jewish Ethics and the Care of End-of-life Patients: A Collection of Rabbinical, Bioethical, Philosophical, and Juristic Opinions. KTAV Publishing House, Inc. ISBN 978-0-88125-921-6. Archived from the original on January 1, 2024. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Boonin, David (2022). "1. Introduction: Sex, Ethics, and Philosophy". In Boonin, David (ed.). The Palgrave Handbook of Sexual Ethics. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-3-030-87786-6. Archived from the original on December 26, 2023. Retrieved December 27, 2023.

Boyd, Craig A.; Timpe, Kevin (2021). The Virtues: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-258407-6. Archived from the original on February 1, 2024. Retrieved December 19, 2023.

Brandon, S. G. F. (1975). "The Idea of the Judgment of the Dead in Ancient Near East". In Hinnells, John R. (ed.). Mithraic Studies: Proceedings of the First International Congress of Mithraic Studies. Manchester University Press. ISBN 978-0-7190-0536-7. Archived from the original on December 18, 2023. Retrieved December 19, 2023.

Brannigan, Michael C. (2010). Striking a Balance: A Primer in Traditional Asian Values. Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 978-0-7391-3846-5. Archived from the original on January 1, 2024. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Braunack-Mayer, A. J.; Street, J. M.; Palmer, N. (1998). "Technology, Ethics Of: Overview". In Chadwick, Ruth (ed.). Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics (2 ed.). Academic Press. ISBN 978-0-12-373932-2.

Brennan, Andrew; Lo, Norva Y. S. (2022). "Environmental Ethics". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on August 4, 2019. Retrieved December 24, 2023.

Brink, David O. (2020). "Consequentialism, the Separateness of Persons, and Aggregation". In Portmore, Douglas W. (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Consequentialism. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-090533-0. Archived from the original on January 2, 2024. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Brown, William P. (2004). The Ten Commandments: The Reciprocity of Faithfulness. Westminster John Knox Press. ISBN 978-0-664-22323-6. Archived from the original on December 31, 2023. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Brown, James Robert; Fehige, Yiftach (2019). "Thought Experiments". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on November 21, 2017. Retrieved October 29, 2021.

Brun, Georg (2017). "Thought Experiments in Ethics". The Routledge Companion to Thought Experiments. Routledge. pp. 195–210. doi:10.4324/9781315175027-12. ISBN 978-1-315-17502-7. Archived from the original on July 7, 2022. Retrieved January 7, 2024.

Bunnin, Nicholas; Yu, Jiyuan (2009). The Blackwell Dictionary of Western Philosophy. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-4051-9112-8. Archived from the original on December 27, 2023. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Byron, Michael (2004). Satisficing and Maximizing: Moral Theorists on Practical Reason. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-01005-4. Archived from the original on January 2, 2024. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Calder, Todd (2022). "The Concept of Evil". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved January 7, 2024.

Calida, Behnido Y. (2022). "System Governance". In Keating, Charles B.; Katina, Polinpapilinho F.; Jr, Charles W. Chesterman; Pyne, James C. (eds.). Complex System Governance: Theory and Practice. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-3-030-93852-9. Archived from the original on January 3, 2024. Retrieved January 4, 2024.

Campbell, Keith (1985). "Self-mastery and Stoic Ethics". Philosophy. 60 (233): 327–340. doi:10.1017/S0031819100070170. S2CID 144863967.

Caro, Mario De; Marraffa, Massimo; Vaccarezza, Maria Silvia (2021). "The Priority of Phronesis: How to Rescue Virtue Theory From Its Critics". In Caro, Mario De; Vaccarezza, Maria Silvia (eds.). Practical Wisdom: Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-000-40605-4. Archived from the original on January 3, 2024. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Catalano, George D. (2022). Engineering Ethics: Peace, Justice, and the Earth, Second Edition. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-3-031-02115-2. Archived from the original on December 24, 2023. Retrieved December 27, 2023.

Chakraborti, Chhanda (2023). Introduction to Ethics: Concepts, Theories, and Contemporary Issues. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-981-99-0707-6. Archived from the original on January 3, 2024. Retrieved December 27, 2023.

Chappell, Sophie-Grace; Smyth, Nicholas (2023). "Bernard Williams". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on July 10, 2022. Retrieved January 8, 2024.

Chowdhury, Sanjoy Barua (2019). "28. Ethical Challenges for Global Education: A Buddhist Perspective". In Thien, Thich Duc; Tu, Thich Nhat (eds.). Buddhist Approach to Global Education in Ethics. Vietnam Buddhist University Publications. ISBN 978-604-89-7928-7. Archived from the original on January 1, 2024. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Christians, Clifford G. (2005). "Communication Ethics". In Mitcham, Carl (ed.). Encyclopedia of Science, Technology and Ethics. 3: L - R. Thomson Gale. ISBN 978-0-02-865834-6. Archived from the original on February 18, 2023. Retrieved December 27, 2023.

Cochrane, Alasdair. "Environmental Ethics". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on June 27, 2019. Retrieved December 24, 2023.

Corbin, Arthur L. (1924). "Rights and Duties". The Yale Law Journal. 33 (5): 501–527. doi:10.2307/788021. JSTOR 788021.

Cowan, Steven B. (2020). "Introduction to Part One". In Cowan, Steven B. (ed.). Problems in Value Theory: An Introduction to Contemporary Debates. Bloomsbury Publishing. ISBN 978-1-350-14741-6. Archived from the original on January 3, 2024. Retrieved January 4, 2024.

Crisp, Roger (2005). "Deontological Ethics". In Honderich, Ted (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7. Archived from the original on January 29, 2021. Retrieved December 19, 2023.

Crisp, Roger (2011). "Ethics". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-L132-2. ISBN 978-0-415-25069-6. Archived from the original on August 1, 2023. Retrieved January 7, 2024.

Cummiskey, David (1996). Kantian Consequentialism. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-509453-4. Archived from the original on January 3, 2024. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Dalal, Neil (2021). "Śaṅkara". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on January 27, 2022. Retrieved December 18, 2023.

Darwall, Stephen L. (2003). "Theories of Ethics". In Frey, R. G.; Wellman, Christopher Heath (eds.). A Companion to Applied Ethics. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-4051-7190-8. Archived from the original on February 1, 2024. Retrieved December 27, 2023.

Das, Kantilal (2021). The Paradigm of Justice: A Contemporary Debate Between John Rawls and Amartya Sen. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-000-43681-5. Archived from the original on December 26, 2023. Retrieved December 26, 2023.

Deigh, John (1999). "Ethics". In Audi, Robert (ed.). The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-107-64379-6. Archived from the original on April 14, 2021. Retrieved January 7, 2024.

DeLapp, Kevin M. "Metaethics". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on January 23, 2024. Retrieved December 19, 2023.

Delden, J. J. M. van (1998). "Euthanasia (Physician-Assisted Suicide)". In Chadwick, Ruth (ed.). Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics (2 ed.). Academic Press. ISBN 978-0-12-373932-2.

Dittmer, Joel. "Ethics, Applied". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on June 1, 2023. Retrieved December 23, 2023.

Doris, John; Stich, Stephen; Phillips, Jonathan; Walmsley, Lachlan (2020). "Moral Psychology: Empirical Approaches". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on November 7, 2019. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Dorsey, Dale (2020). "Consequences". In Portmore, Douglas W. (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Consequentialism. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-090534-7. Archived from the original on January 2, 2024. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Downie, R. S. (2005). "Ethics and Morality". In Honderich, Ted (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7. Archived from the original on January 29, 2021. Retrieved December 19, 2023.

Dreier, James (2007). "Moral Relativism and Moral Nihilism". In Copp, David (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195325911.003.0010. ISBN 978-0-19-989207-5.

Dueñas, María del Pilar Muñoz; Lucia, Aiello; Rosario, Cabrita; Mauro, Gatti (2018). Corporate Social Responsibility for Valorization of Cultural Organizations. IGI Global. ISBN 978-1-5225-3552-2. Archived from the original on December 25, 2023. Retrieved December 27, 2023.

Edmundson, William A. (2004). An Introduction to Rights. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-00870-9. Archived from the original on January 2, 2024. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Elrod, Edwin M.; Smith, Martha M. (2005). "Information Ethics". In Mitcham, Carl (ed.). Encyclopedia of Science, Technology and Ethics. 3: L - R. Thomson Gale. ISBN 978-0-02-865834-6. Archived from the original on December 26, 2023. Retrieved December 27, 2023.

Eysenck, Michael W. (2004). Psychology: An International Perspective. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-1-84169-361-3. Archived from the original on January 3, 2024. Retrieved January 4, 2024.

Feibleman, James K. (1967). "Rights and Duties". Moral Strategy: An Introduction to the Ethics of Confrontation. Springer Netherlands. pp. 121–126. doi:10.1007/978-94-011-9321-4_10. ISBN 978-94-011-8559-2. Archived from the original on January 7, 2024. Retrieved January 7, 2024.

Finlayson, James Gordon; Rees, Dafydd Huw (2023). "Jürgen Habermas". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on July 8, 2023. Retrieved December 31, 2023.

FitzPatrick, William J. (2011). "Ethical Non-Naturalism and Normative Properties". In Brady, Michael (ed.). New Waves in Metaethics. Palgrave Macmillan UK. pp. 7–35. doi:10.1057/9780230294899_2. ISBN 978-0-230-29489-9. Archived from the original on February 1, 2024. Retrieved December 22, 2023.

Flynn, Eileen P. (2012). Ethical Lessons of the Financial Crisis. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-136-34312-4. Archived from the original on December 31, 2023. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Fotion, N. (1998). "Military Ethics". In Chadwick, Ruth (ed.). Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics (2 ed.). Academic Press. ISBN 978-0-12-373932-2.

Francione, Gary L. (2004). "Animals - Property or Persons?". In Sunstein, Cass R.; Nussbaum, Martha C. (eds.). Animal Rights: Current Debates and New Directions. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-803473-5. Archived from the original on December 26, 2023. Retrieved December 27, 2023.

Frowe, Helen (2021). "The Ethics of War". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on June 8, 2023. Retrieved December 25, 2023.

Funk, Michael (2021). "What Is Robot Ethics? ... And Can It Be Standardized?". In Nørskov, M.; Seibt, J.; Quick, O. S. (eds.). Culturally Sustainable Social Robotics: Proceedings of Robophilosophy 2020. IOS Press. ISBN 978-1-64368-155-9. Archived from the original on January 4, 2024. Retrieved January 4, 2024.

Gay, William C. (2006). "A Normative Framework for Addressing Peace and Related Global Issues". In Boersema, David; Brown, Katy Gray (eds.). Spiritual and Political Dimensions of Nonviolence and Peace. Rodopi. ISBN 978-90-420-2061-0. Archived from the original on December 26, 2023. Retrieved December 27, 2023.

Gillon, R. (1998). "Bioethics, Overview". In Chadwick, Ruth (ed.). Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics (2 ed.). Academic Press. ISBN 978-0-12-373932-2.

Gordon, John-Stewart. "Bioethics". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on October 27, 2023. Retrieved December 23, 2023.

Gowans, Chris (2021). "Moral Relativism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on February 1, 2024. Retrieved December 19, 2023.

Grayling, A. C. (2019). The History of Philosophy. Penguin UK. ISBN 978-0-241-98086-6. Archived from the original on July 3, 2023. Retrieved May 24, 2023.

Grenz, Stanley J.; Guretzki, David; Nordling, Cherith Fee (2010). Pocket Dictionary of Theological Terms. InterVarsity Press. ISBN 978-0-8308-6707-3. Archived from the original on January 3, 2024. Retrieved January 4, 2024.

Gustafson, Andrew B. (2020). "Normative Ethics". Encyclopedia of Business and Professional Ethics. Springer International Publishing. pp. 1–5. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-23514-1_1222-1. ISBN 978-3-319-23514-1. S2CID 243173997. Archived from the original on December 28, 2023. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Gustafsson, Juuso-Ville; Pietarinen, Ahti-Veikko (2016). "8. Is Ethical Normativity Similar to Logical Normativity?". In West, Donna E.; Anderson, Myrdene (eds.). Consensus on Peirce's Concept of Habit: Before and Beyond Consciousness. Springer. ISBN 978-3-319-45920-2. Archived from the original on January 3, 2024. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Haiming, Wang (2021). The Principles of New Ethics. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-138-33161-7.

Haines, William. "Consequentialism and Utilitarianism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on December 24, 2023. Retrieved December 28, 2023.

Hale, Benjamin (2017). "Duty & Obligation: Rights, Rules, and Respect for Nature". In Gardiner, Stephen Mark; Thompson, Allen (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Environmental Ethics. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-994133-9. Archived from the original on January 3, 2024. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Hall, Edward; Sabl, Andrew (2022). Hall, Edward; Sabl, Andrew (eds.). Political Ethics: A Handbook. Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0-691-23131-0. Archived from the original on December 26, 2023. Retrieved December 27, 2023.

Harrison, Ross (2005). "Meta-ethics". In Honderich, Ted (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7. Archived from the original on January 29, 2021. Retrieved December 19, 2023.

Heyd, David (2019). "Supererogation". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved January 7, 2024.

Hirose, Iwao; Olson, Jonas (2015). "Introduction to Value Theory". In Hirose, Iwao; Olson, Jonas (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-022143-0. Archived from the original on January 3, 2024. Retrieved January 4, 2024.

Hoad, T. F. (1993). The Concise Oxford Dictionary of English Etymology. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-283098-2.

Hollenbach, David (2002). The Common Good and Christian Ethics. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-89451-7. Archived from the original on January 10, 2024. Retrieved January 10, 2024.

Holmes, Robert L. (2018). Introduction to Applied Ethics. Bloomsbury Academic. ISBN 978-1-3500-2980-4.

Hooker, Brad (2023). "Rule Consequentialism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on February 1, 2024. Retrieved December 29, 2023.

Hooker, Brad (2005). "Consequentialism". In Honderich, Ted (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7. Archived from the original on January 29, 2021. Retrieved December 19, 2023.

Hooker, Brad (2014). "Utilitarianism and Fairness". In Eggleston, Ben; Miller, Dale E. (eds.). The Cambridge Companion to Utilitarianism. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-139-86748-1. Archived from the original on January 3, 2024. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Hursthouse, Rosalind (1999). On Virtue Ethics. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-823818-8. Archived from the original on January 1, 2024. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Hursthouse, Rosalind; Pettigrove, Glen (2023). "Virtue Ethics". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on May 14, 2019. Retrieved December 31, 2023.

Imafidon, E. (2015). The Ethics of Subjectivity: Perspectives Since the Dawn of Modernity. Springer. ISBN 978-1-137-47242-7. Archived from the original on December 18, 2023. Retrieved December 19, 2023.

Jankowiak, Tim. "Kant, Immanuel". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on December 19, 2023. Retrieved December 30, 2023.

Johnson, Robert; Cureton, Adam (2022). "Kant's Moral Philosophy". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on February 1, 2024. Retrieved December 30, 2023.

Kagan, Shelly (1998). Normative Ethics. Westview Press. ISBN 978-0-8133-0846-3.

Karenga, Maulana (2004). Maat, the Moral Ideal in Ancient Egypt: A Study in Classical African Ethics. Psychology Press. ISBN 978-0-415-94753-4. Archived from the original on December 18, 2023. Retrieved December 19, 2023.

Kendall, Sacha (2017). "13. Postmodern Ethics for Practice". In Hugman, Richard; Carter, Jan (eds.). Rethinking Values and Ethics in Social Work. Bloomsbury Publishing. ISBN 978-1-137-45503-1. Archived from the original on December 31, 2023. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Kivy, Peter (2011). Antithetical Arts: On the Ancient Quarrel Between Literature and Music. OUP Oxford. ISBN 978-0-19-161575-7. Archived from the original on December 30, 2023. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Kraut, Richard (2022). "Aristotle's Ethics". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on November 10, 2022. Retrieved January 1, 2024.

Krellenstein, Marc (2017). "Moral Nihilism and Its Implications". The Journal of Mind and Behavior. 38 (1): 75–90. ISSN 0271-0137. JSTOR 44631529. Archived from the original on December 20, 2023. Retrieved December 22, 2023.

Kriegel, Uri (1999). "Normativity and Rationality: Bernard Williams on Reasons for Action". Iyyun: The Jerusalem Philosophical Quarterly / עיון: רבעון פילוסופי. 48: 281–292. ISSN 0021-3306. JSTOR 23352588.

Kumm, Mattias; Walen, Alec D. (2014). "Human Dignity and Proportionality: Deontic Pluralism in Balancing". In Huscroft, Grant; Miller, Bradley W.; Webber, Grégoire (eds.). Proportionality and the Rule of Law: Rights, Justification, Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-139-95287-3. Archived from the original on January 3, 2024. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Kupperman, Joel J. (2005). "Axiological Ethics". In Honderich, Ted (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7. Archived from the original on January 29, 2021. Retrieved December 19, 2023.

Kvalnes, Øyvind (2023). "Communication Ethics". Communication Climate at Work: Fostering Friendly Friction in Organisations. Springer International Publishing. pp. 101–110. doi:10.1007/978-3-031-28971-2_12. ISBN 978-3-031-28971-2. Archived from the original on December 25, 2023. Retrieved December 27, 2023.

LaFollette, Hugh (2007). "Pragmatic Ethics". In LaFollette, Hugh (ed.). The Blackwell Guide to Ethical Theory. Blackwell. ISBN 978-0-631-20119-9. Archived from the original on May 16, 2023. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Lazar, Seth (2020). "War". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on August 9, 2023. Retrieved December 25, 2023.

Lazari-Radek, Katarzyna de; Singer, Peter (2017). "Parfit on Objectivity and 'The Profoundest Problem of Ethics'". In Singer, Peter (ed.). Does Anything Really Matter?: Essays on Parfit on Objectivity. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-108439-3. Archived from the original on December 26, 2023. Retrieved December 26, 2023.

Legg, Catherine; Hookway, Christopher (2021). "Pragmatism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on October 8, 2020. Retrieved December 31, 2023.

Liddell, Henry George; Scott, Robert (1889). An Intermediate Greek-English Lexicon. New York, Harper & Brothers. OCLC 1146511662.

Linn, Ruth (1994). "Moral Disobedience During the Lebanon War: What Can the Cognitive-Developmental Approach Learn from the Experience of Israeli Soldiers?". In Puka, Bill (ed.). Moral Development: New Research in Moral Development. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-0-8153-1552-0. Archived from the original on January 3, 2024. Retrieved January 4, 2024.

Littlejohn, Ronnie. "Chinese Philosophy: Overview of History". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on June 1, 2023. Retrieved June 12, 2023.

Lloyd, Andrew; Hansen, John (2003). "Philosophical Foundations of Professional Ethics". In O'Donohue, William; Ferguson, Kyle E. (eds.). Handbook of Professional Ethics for Psychologists: Issues, Questions, and Controversies. Sage. ISBN 978-0-7619-1189-0. Archived from the original on February 1, 2024. Retrieved January 7, 2024.

Lutz, Matthew (2023). "Moral Naturalism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on October 2, 2019. Retrieved December 20, 2023.

Matsuba, M. Kyle; Murzyn, Theresa; Hart, Daniel (2011). "A Model of Moral Identity". Advances in Child Development and Behavior. 40: 181–207. doi:10.1016/b978-0-12-386491-8.00005-0. ISBN 978-0-12-386491-8. PMID 21887962.

Mattila, Janne (2022). The Eudaimonist Ethics of al-Fārābī and Avicenna. Brill. ISBN 978-90-04-50691-6. Archived from the original on December 18, 2023. Retrieved December 19, 2023.

Maxwell, Bruce (2023). "Educational Ethics". In Poff, Deborah C.; Michalos, Alex C. (eds.). Encyclopedia of Business and Professional Ethics. Springer International Publishing. pp. 609–614. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-22767-8_1323. ISBN 978-3-030-22767-8. Archived from the original on December 26, 2023. Retrieved December 27, 2023.

McDonald, Fritz J. (2017). "4. Beyond Objectivism and Subjectivism". In Makowski, Piotr (ed.). Praxiology and the Reasons for Action. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-351-49716-9. Archived from the original on December 26, 2023. Retrieved December 26, 2023.

McEwan, Tom (2001). Managing Values and Beliefs in Organisations. Prentice Hall. ISBN 978-0-273-64340-1. Archived from the original on December 31, 2023. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

McNamara, Paul; Van De Putte, Frederik (2022). "Deontic Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on February 1, 2024. Retrieved January 7, 2024.

McNaughton, David; Rawling, Piers (1998). Consequentialism. Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on January 2, 2024. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Medvecky, Fabien; Leach, Joan (2019). An Ethics of Science Communication. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-3-030-32116-1. Archived from the original on December 27, 2023. Retrieved December 27, 2023.

Mentan, Tatah (2022). Understanding Contemporary Journalism: A Handbook of Principles and Practice. African Books Collective. ISBN 978-9956-552-91-7. Archived from the original on December 26, 2023. Retrieved December 27, 2023.

Mesoudi, Alex; Danielson, Peter (2008). "Ethics, Evolution and Culture". Theory in Biosciences. 127 (3): 229–240. doi:10.1007/s12064-008-0027-y. PMID 18357481. S2CID 18643499.

Metselaar, Suzanne; Widdershoven, Guy (2016). "Discourse Ethics". Encyclopedia of Global Bioethics. Springer International Publishing. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-09483-0_145. ISBN 978-3-319-09483-0. Archived from the original on December 31, 2023. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Meyer, Kirsten (2023). "Moral Education Through the Fostering of Reasoning Skills". Ethical Theory and Moral Practice. doi:10.1007/s10677-023-10367-3.

Meynell, Letitia; Paron, Clarisse (2023). Applied Ethics Primer. Broadview Press. ISBN 978-1-77048-899-1. Archived from the original on December 23, 2023. Retrieved December 27, 2023.

Milevski, Voin (February 17, 2017). "Weakness of will and motivational internalism". Philosophical Psychology. 30 (1–2). doi:10.1080/09515089.2016.1255317.

Miller, Christian B. (2023). "Overview of Contemporary Metaethics and Normative Ethical Theory". In Miller, Christian B. (ed.). The Bloomsbury Handbook of Ethics. Bloomsbury Publishing. ISBN 978-1-350-21790-4. Archived from the original on December 20, 2023. Retrieved December 22, 2023.

Mitcham, Carl (2022). Thinking Through Technology: The Path Between Engineering and Philosophy. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-82539-7. Archived from the original on December 25, 2023. Retrieved December 27, 2023.

Monzon, Jorge E. (2012). "Bioethics". In Abu-Faraj, Ziad O. (ed.). Handbook of Research on Biomedical Engineering Education and Advanced Bioengineering Learning: Interdisciplinary Concepts: Interdisciplinary Concepts. IGI Global. ISBN 978-1-4666-0123-9. Archived from the original on January 4, 2024. Retrieved January 4, 2024.

Moore, Andrew (2019). "Hedonism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on September 18, 2018. Retrieved December 31, 2023.

Morales, Maria H. (2005). Mill's The Subjection of Women. Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 978-0-7425-3518-3. Archived from the original on December 30, 2023. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Moreland, J. P.; Craig, William Lane (2017). Philosophical Foundations for a Christian Worldview. InterVarsity Press. ISBN 978-0-8308-8917-4. Archived from the original on December 22, 2023. Retrieved December 22, 2023.

Mulvaney, Robert J. (2009). Classical Philosophical Questions (13 ed.). Prentice Hall. ISBN 978-0-13-600652-7.

Murphy, Mark (2019). "Theological Voluntarism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on August 3, 2019. Retrieved December 31, 2023.

Myers, Jeff; Noebel, David A. (2015). Understanding the Times: A Survey of Competing Worldviews. David C. Cook. ISBN 978-0-7814-1378-7. Archived from the original on December 31, 2023. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Nafsika Athanassoulis. "Virtue Ethics". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on April 27, 2023. Retrieved December 31, 2023.

Nagel, Thomas (2006). "Ethics". In Borchert, Donald (ed.). Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. ISBN 978-0-02-865790-5. Archived from the original on August 24, 2018. Retrieved January 7, 2024.

Norlock, Kathryn (2019). "Feminist Ethics". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on September 11, 2018. Retrieved December 18, 2023.

Norman, Richard (2005). "Moral Philosophy, History of". In Honderich, Ted (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7. Archived from the original on January 29, 2021. Retrieved December 19, 2023.

O'Neill, Onora. "Kantian Ethics". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on December 30, 2023. Retrieved December 30, 2023.

O'Neill, Onora (2013). "Duty and Obligation". In Becker, Lawrence C.; Becker, Charlotte B. (eds.). Encyclopedia of Ethics. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-135-35096-3. Archived from the original on February 1, 2024. Retrieved January 7, 2024.

Oosthuizen, Lucas M. (2002). Media Ethics in the South African Context: An Introduction and Overview. Juta and Company Ltd. ISBN 978-0-7021-5657-1. Archived from the original on January 1, 2024. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Ortiz, Melba Vélez (2020). "Preface". Maatian Ethics in a Communication Context. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-000-04831-5. Archived from the original on December 18, 2023. Retrieved December 19, 2023.

Parker, Christine; Evans, Adrian (2007). Inside Lawyers' Ethics. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-139-46128-3. Archived from the original on February 1, 2024. Retrieved December 27, 2023.

Patching, Roger; Hirst, Martin (2013). Journalism Ethics: Arguments and Cases for the Twenty-first Century. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-96374-5. Archived from the original on December 26, 2023. Retrieved December 27, 2023.

Paul, Richard W.; Elder, Linda (2005). The Miniature Guide to Understanding the Foundations of Ethical Reasoning: Based on "Critical Thinking Concepts & Principles" (3. ed.). Foundation for Critical Thinking. ISBN 978-0-944583-17-3.

Pera, Silvia Angelina; Tonder, Susara Van (2005). Ethics in Health Care. Juta and Company Ltd. ISBN 978-0-7021-6679-2. Archived from the original on January 1, 2024. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Perrett, Roy W. (2016). An Introduction to Indian Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-85356-9. Archived from the original on June 22, 2023. Retrieved June 9, 2023.

Petersen, Thomas Søbirk; Ryberg, Jesper (2022). "Applied Ethics". Oxford Bibliographies. Archived from the original on December 28, 2023. Retrieved December 23, 2023.

Peterson, Anna L. (2020). "4. Pragmatism and Ethics: The Path of Inquiry". Works Righteousness: Material Practice in Ethical Theory. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-753225-6. Archived from the original on December 31, 2023. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Pick, Thomas (2004). "Moral Obligation". Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement. 54: 159–185. doi:10.1017/S1358246100008493. S2CID 1105915.

Porter, Burton (2010). What the Tortoise Taught Us: The Story of Philosophy. Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. ISBN 978-1-4422-0553-6. Archived from the original on January 1, 2024. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Post, Stephen G. (2011). "Sorokin and the Therapeutic of Love: A Critical Assessment". In Aviñó, Elvira del Pozo (ed.). Integralism, Altruism and Reconstruction: Essays in Honor of Pitirim A. Sorokin. Universitat de València. ISBN 978-84-370-8362-9. Archived from the original on January 4, 2024. Retrieved January 4, 2024.

Puka, William. "Moral Development". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on January 3, 2024. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Ranganathan, Shyam. "Ramanuja". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on February 12, 2020. Retrieved December 18, 2023.

Reilly, R. (1977). "Socrates' Moral Paradox". The Southwestern Journal of Philosophy. 8 (1). doi:10.5840/swjphil19778110. ISSN 0038-481X.

Rendtorff, J. D. (1998). "Business Ethics, Overview". In Chadwick, Ruth (ed.). Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics (2 ed.). Academic Press. ISBN 978-0-12-373932-2.

Ribino, Patrizia; Lodato, Carmelo (2019). "A Norm Compliance Approach for Open and Goal-Directed Intelligent Systems". Complexity. 2019: 1–20. doi:10.1155/2019/7895875.

Rice, Stanley A. (2009). Encyclopedia of Evolution. Infobase Publishing. ISBN 978-1-4381-1005-9. Archived from the original on January 4, 2024. Retrieved January 4, 2024.

Ridge, Michael (2019). "Moral Non-Naturalism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved December 20, 2023.

Rini, Regina A. "Morality and Cognitive Science". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on September 7, 2023. Retrieved September 7, 2023.

Robson, Gregory J.; Tsou, Jonathan Y. (2023). Technology Ethics: A Philosophical Introduction and Readings. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-1-000-83023-1. Archived from the original on December 26, 2023. Retrieved December 27, 2023.

Rosati, Connie S. (2016). "Moral Motivation". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on July 16, 2023. Retrieved December 21, 2023.

Rudy-Hiller, Fernando (2022). "27. The Moral Psychology of Moral Responsibility". In Vargas, Manuel; Doris, John (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Moral Psychology. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-887171-2. Archived from the original on January 3, 2024. Retrieved January 4, 2024.

Ryberg, Jesper (2010). Applied Ethics: Oxford Bibliographies Online Research Guide. Oxford University Press, USA. ISBN 978-0-19-980865-6. Archived from the original on December 25, 2023. Retrieved December 27, 2023.

Sajoo, Amyn (2008). Muslim Ethics: Emerging Vistas. Bloomsbury Publishing. ISBN 978-0-85771-495-4. Archived from the original on December 18, 2023. Retrieved December 19, 2023.

Sander-Staudt, Maureen. "Care Ethics". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on June 4, 2022. Retrieved December 31, 2023.

Sandler, R. (1998). "Environmental Ethics, Overview". In Chadwick, Ruth (ed.). Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics (2 ed.). Academic Press. ISBN 978-0-12-373932-2.

Sayre-McCord, Geoff (2023). "Metaethics". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on July 12, 2023. Retrieved December 19, 2023.

Sayre-McCord, Geoff (2023a). "Moral Realism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on April 23, 2020. Retrieved December 19, 2023.

Schroeder, Mark (2021). "Value Theory". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on February 1, 2024. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Schroeder, Doris. "Evolutionary Ethics". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on September 28, 2023. Retrieved January 4, 2024.

Shafer-Landau, Russ (2020). Oxford Studies in Metaethics Volume 15. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-260331-9. Archived from the original on December 20, 2023. Retrieved December 22, 2023.

Shaver, Robert (2023). "Egoism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on March 24, 2022. Retrieved December 31, 2023.

Simpson, David L. "Ross, William David". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on June 20, 2019. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Sims, Ronald R. (2017). A Contemporary Look at Business Ethics. IAP. ISBN 978-1-68123-956-9. Archived from the original on December 28, 2023. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Singer, Peter (2016). Famine, Affluence, and Morality. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-021920-8.

Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter (2019). "Moral Skepticism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on August 6, 2019. Retrieved December 21, 2023.

Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter (2023). "Consequentialism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on June 18, 2023. Retrieved December 28, 2023.

Slingerland, Edward (2007). Effortless Action: Wu-wei As Conceptual Metaphor and Spiritual Ideal in Early China. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-987457-6. Archived from the original on June 13, 2023. Retrieved December 19, 2023.

Slote, Michael (2005). "Utilitarianism". In Honderich, Ted (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7. Archived from the original on January 29, 2021. Retrieved December 19, 2023.

Slote, Michael (2005a). "Virtues". In Honderich, Ted (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7. Archived from the original on January 29, 2021. Retrieved December 19, 2023.

Smith, Kimberly K. (2018). Exploring Environmental Ethics: An Introduction. Springer. ISBN 978-3-319-77395-7. Archived from the original on December 24, 2023. Retrieved December 27, 2023.

Smith, Barry; Thomas, Alan. "Axiology". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on November 30, 2023. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Sorabji, Richard; Rodin, David (2007). "Introduction". In Sorabji, Richard; Rodin, David (eds.). The Ethics of War: Shared Problems in Different Traditions (Repr ed.). Ashgate Publishing. ISBN 978-0-7546-5448-3.

Stecker, Robert (2010). "Ethics and Aesthetics". In Skorupski, John (ed.). The Routledge Companion to Ethics. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-136-96421-3. Archived from the original on January 3, 2024. Retrieved January 4, 2024.

Stephens, William O. "Stoic Ethics". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

Stoljar, Samuel (1984). "Rights and Duties". An Analysis of Rights. Palgrave Macmillan UK. pp. 36–50. doi:10.1007/978-1-349-17607-6_4. ISBN 978-1-349-17607-6. Archived from the original on June 17, 2018. Retrieved January 7, 2024.

Sullivan, Barbara (2001). "'It's All in the Contract': Rethinking Feminist Critiques of Contract". In Carney, Terry; Ramia, Gaby; Yeatman, Anna (eds.). Contractualism and Citizenship. Federation Press. ISBN 978-1-86287-366-7. Archived from the original on January 3, 2024. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Sulmasy, Daniel P.; Sugarman, Jeremy (2010). "The Many Methods of Medical Ethics (Or, Thirteen Ways of Looking at a Blackbird)". In Sugarman, Jeremy; Sulmasy, Daniel P. (eds.). Methods in Medical Ethics: Second Edition. Georgetown University Press. ISBN 978-1-58901-623-1. Archived from the original on January 1, 2024. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Talbert, Matthew (2019). "Moral Responsibility". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on February 1, 2024. Retrieved January 7, 2024.

Tebbit, Mark (2013). The Philosophy of Law: An Encyclopedia. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-135-58277-7. Archived from the original on June 22, 2023. Retrieved June 10, 2023.

ten Have, Henk; Patrão Neves, Maria do Céu (2021). "Information Ethics". Dictionary of Global Bioethics. Springer International Publishing. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-54161-3_310. ISBN 978-3-030-54161-3. S2CID 241302927. Archived from the original on December 25, 2023. Retrieved December 27, 2023.

Thapar, Romila (1978). Ancient Indian Social History: Some Interpretations. Orient Blackswan. ISBN 978-81-250-0808-8. Archived from the original on December 18, 2023. Retrieved December 19, 2023.

Thoma, Stephen J. (2015). "13 A Neo-Kohlbergian Tale of Two Sensitivities". In Mower, Deborah; Robison, Wade L.; Vandenberg, Phyllis (eds.). Developing Moral Sensitivity. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-49841-4. Archived from the original on January 3, 2024. Retrieved January 4, 2024.

Thomas, Alan (2022). "Normative Ethics". Oxford Bibliographies. Archived from the original on February 1, 2024. Retrieved December 28, 2023.

Tzafestas, Spyros G. (2015). Roboethics: A Navigating Overview. Springer. ISBN 978-3-319-21714-7. Archived from the original on December 25, 2023. Retrieved December 27, 2023.

Verhoeven, F. R. J. (2013). Islam: Its Origin and Spread in Words, Maps and Pictures. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-54091-4. Archived from the original on January 1, 2024. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Vogt, Katja Maria (2017). Desiring the Good: Ancient Proposals and Contemporary Theory. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-069248-3. Archived from the original on February 1, 2024. Retrieved January 10, 2024.

Wenar, Leif (2021). "John Rawls". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on September 23, 2018. Retrieved December 26, 2023.

Westacott, Emrys. "Moral Relativism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on December 16, 2023. Retrieved December 19, 2023.

Williams, Garrath. "Praise and Blame". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on November 30, 2023. Retrieved January 7, 2024.

Wilson, Scott D. "Animals and Ethics". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on July 15, 2023. Retrieved December 24, 2023.

Winkler, E. R. (1998). "Applied Ethics, Overview". In Chadwick, Ruth (ed.). Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics (2 ed.). Academic Press. ISBN 978-0-12-373932-2. Archived from the original on December 23, 2023. Retrieved December 27, 2023.

Wolfendale, Jessica (2007). "Professional Ethics and the Military". Torture and the Military Profession. Palgrave Macmillan UK. pp. 47–76. doi:10.1057/9780230592803_4. ISBN 978-0-230-59280-3. Archived from the original on December 25, 2023. Retrieved December 27, 2023.

Woollard, Fiona; Howard-Snyder, Frances (2022). "Doing Vs. Allowing Harm". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on October 5, 2023. Retrieved September 7, 2023.

Wu, Jiyun; Wokutch, Richard E. (2008). "Confucianism". In Kolb, Robert W. (ed.). Encyclopedia of Business Ethics and Society. Sage. ISBN 978-1-4129-1652-3. Archived from the original on January 1, 2024. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Yount, Lisa (2007). Animal Rights. Infobase Publishing. ISBN 978-1-4381-3063-7. Archived from the original on December 24, 2023. Retrieved December 27, 2023.

Zhang, Feng (2023). "The Conception of Morality in Moral Realism". In Xuetong, Yan; Yuanyuan, Fang (eds.). The Essence of Interstate Leadership: Debating Moral Realism. Policy Press. ISBN 978-1-5292-3263-9. Archived from the original on December 30, 2023. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

Zimmerman, Michael J. (2015). "Value and Normativity". In Hirose, Iwao; Olson, Jonas (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory. Oxford university press. ISBN 978-0-19-995930-3.

Zimmerman, Michael J.; Bradley, Ben (2019). "Intrinsic Vs. Extrinsic Value". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved January 3, 2024.

External links[edit]

Ethics at Wikipedia's sister projects

Definitions from WiktionaryMedia from CommonsQuotations from WikiquoteTexts from WikisourceTextbooks from WikibooksResources from WikiversityData from Wikidata

Library resources about Ethics

Resources in your library

Resources in other libraries

Meta-Ethics at PhilPapers

Normative Ethics at PhilPapers

Applied Ethics at PhilPapers

Ethics at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project

vteEthicsNormative

Consequentialism

Deontology

Care

Particularism

Pragmatic

Role

Suffering-focused

Utilitarianism

Virtue

Applied

Animal

Artificial intelligence

Bio

Business

Discourse

Engineering

Environmental

Legal

Machine

Meat eating

Media

Medical

Nursing

Professional

Sexual

Technology

Terraforming

Uncertain sentience

Meta

Absolutism

Axiology

Cognitivism

Realism

Naturalism

Non-naturalism

Subjectivism

Ideal observer theory

Divine command theory

Constructivism

Euthyphro dilemma

Intuitionism

Nihilism

Non-cognitivism

Emotivism

Expressivism

Quasi-realism

Universal prescriptivism

Rationalism

Relativism

Skepticism

Universalism

Value monism – Value pluralism

Schools

Buddhist

Christian

Confucian

Epicurean

Existentialist

Feminist

Islamic

Jewish

Kantian

Rousseauian

Stoic

Tao

Concepts

Authority

Autonomy

Common sense

Compassion

Conscience

Consent

Culture of life

Dignity

Double standard

Duty

Equality

Etiquette

Eudaimonia

Family values

Fidelity

Free will

Good and evil

Good

Evil

Problem of evil

Happiness

Honour

Ideal

Immorality

Justice

Liberty

Loyalty

Moral courage

Moral hierarchy

Moral imperative

Morality

Norm

Political freedom

Precept

Rights

Self-discipline

Suffering

Stewardship

Sympathy

Theodicy

Trust

Value

Intrinsic

Japan

Western

Vice

Virtue

Vow

Wrong

Ethicists

Laozi

Socrates

Plato

Aristotle

Diogenes

Valluvar

Cicero

Confucius

Augustine

Mencius

Mozi

Xunzi

Aquinas

Spinoza

Hume

Kant

Hegel

Schopenhauer

Bentham

Mill

Kierkegaard

Sidgwick

Nietzsche

Moore

Barth

Tillich

Bonhoeffer

Foot

Rawls

Dewey

Williams

Mackie

Anscombe

Frankena

MacIntyre

Hare

Singer

Parfit

Nagel

Adams

Taylor

Azurmendi

Korsgaard

Nussbaum

Works

Nicomachean Ethics (c. 322 BC)

Ethics (Spinoza) (1677)

A Treatise of Human Nature (1740)

The Theory of Moral Sentiments (1759)

Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (1785)

Critique of Practical Reason (1788)

Elements of the Philosophy of Right (1820)

Either/Or (1843)

Utilitarianism (1861)

Beyond Good and Evil (1886)

On the Genealogy of Morality (1887)

Principia Ethica (1903)

Ethics (Moore) (1912)

A Theory of Justice (1971)

Animal Liberation (1975)

Practical Ethics (1979)

After Virtue (1981)

Related

Axiology

Casuistry

Descriptive ethics

Ethics in religion

Evolutionary ethics

History of ethics

Ideology

Moral psychology

Philosophy of law

Political philosophy

Population ethics

Secular ethics

Social philosophy

Index

Category

vtePhilosophyBranchesBranches

Aesthetics

Applied philosophy

Epistemology

Ethics

Logic

Metaphilosophy

Metaphysics

Philosophy of language

Philosophy of mathematics

Philosophy of mind

Philosophy of religion

Philosophy of science

Political philosophy

Practical philosophy

Social philosophy

Theoretical philosophy

Aesthetics

Aesthetic response

Formalism

Institutionalism

Epistemology

Empiricism

Fideism

Naturalism

Particularism

Rationalism

Skepticism

Solipsism

Ethics

Consequentialism

Deontology

Virtue

Free will

Compatibilism

Determinism

Hard

Incompatibilism

Hard

Libertarianism

Metaphysics

Atomism

Dualism

Idealism

Monism

Naturalism

Realism

Mind

Behaviorism

Eliminativism

Emergentism

Epiphenomenalism

Functionalism

Objectivism

Subjectivism

Normativity

Absolutism

Particularism

Relativism

Nihilism

Skepticism

Universalism

Ontology

Action

Event

Process

Reality

Anti-realism

Conceptualism

Idealism

Materialism

Naturalism

Nominalism

Physicalism

Realism

By eraBy era

Ancient

Western

Medieval

Renaissance

Early modern

Modern

Contemporary

AncientChinese

Agriculturalism

Confucianism

Legalism

Logicians

Mohism

Chinese naturalism

Taoism

Yangism

Greco-Roman

Presocratic

Ionians

Pythagoreans

Eleatics

Atomists

Sophists

Cyrenaics

Cynicism

Eretrian school

Megarian school

Academy

Peripatetic school

Hellenistic philosophy

Pyrrhonism

Stoicism

Epicureanism

Academic Skepticism

Middle Platonism

School of the Sextii

Neopythagoreanism

Second Sophistic

Neoplatonism

Church Fathers

Indian

Hindu

Samkhya

Nyaya

Vaisheshika

Yoga

Mīmāṃsā

Ājīvika

Ajñana

Cārvāka

Jain

Anekantavada

Syādvāda

Buddhist

Abhidharma

Sarvāstivadā

Pudgalavada

Sautrāntika

Madhyamaka

Svatantrika and Prasangika

Śūnyatā

Yogacara

Tibetan

Persian

Mazdakism

Mithraism

Zoroastrianism

Zurvanism

MedievalEast Asian

Neotaoism

Tiantai

Huayan

Chan

Zen

Neo-Confucianism

Korean Confucianism

European

Christian

Augustinianism

Scholasticism

Thomism

Scotism

Occamism

Renaissance humanism

Indian

Vedanta

Acintya bheda abheda

Advaita

Bhedabheda

Dvaita

Nimbarka Sampradaya

Shuddhadvaita

Vishishtadvaita

Navya-Nyāya

Islamic

Aristotelianism

Averroism

Avicennism

Illuminationism

ʿIlm al-Kalām

Sufi

Jewish

Judeo-Islamic

Modern

Anarchism

Classical Realism

Collectivism

Conservatism

Determinism

Dualism

Edo neo-Confucianism

Empiricism

Existentialism

Foundationalism

Historicism

Holism

Humanism

Anti-

Idealism

Absolute

British

German

Objective

Subjective

Transcendental

Individualism

Kokugaku

Liberalism

Materialism

Modernism

Monism

Naturalism

Natural law

Nihilism

New Confucianism

Neo-scholasticism

Pragmatism

Phenomenology

Positivism

Reductionism

Rationalism

Social contract

Socialism

Transcendentalism

Utilitarianism

People

Cartesianism

Kantianism

Neo

Kierkegaardianism

Krausism

Hegelianism

Marxism

Newtonianism

Nietzscheanism

Spinozism

ContemporaryAnalytic

Applied ethics

Analytic feminism

Analytical Marxism

Communitarianism

Consequentialism

Critical rationalism

Experimental philosophy

Falsificationism

Foundationalism / Coherentism

Internalism and externalism

Logical positivism

Legal positivism

Meta-ethics

Moral realism

Quinean naturalism

Normative ethics

Ordinary language philosophy

Postanalytic philosophy

Quietism

Rawlsian

Reformed epistemology

Systemics

Scientism

Scientific realism

Scientific skepticism

Transactionalism

Contemporary utilitarianism

Vienna Circle

Wittgensteinian

Continental

Critical theory

Deconstruction

Existentialism

Feminist

Frankfurt School

Hermeneutics

Neo-Marxism

New Historicism

Phenomenology

Posthumanism

Postmodernism

Post-structuralism

Social constructionism

Structuralism

Western Marxism

Miscellaneous

Kyoto School

Objectivism

Postcritique

Russian cosmism

more...

By regionBy regionAfrican

Bantu

Egyptian

Ethiopian

Africana

Eastern

Buddhist

Chinese

Indian

Indonesian

Japanese

Korean

Taiwanese

Vietnamese

Middle Eastern

Iranian

Islamic

Jewish

Pakistani

Turkish

Western

American

Australian

British

Scottish

Canada

Czech

Danish

Dutch

French

German

Greek

Italian

Maltese

Polish

Slovene

Spanish

Miscellaneous

Amerindian

Aztec

Romanian

Russian

Yugoslav

 Philosophy portal

Category

vteSocial philosophyConcepts

Anomie

Convention

Customs

Cultural heritage

Culturalism

Inter

Mono

Multi

Culture

Counter

Familialism

History

Honour

Human nature

Identity

Formation

Ideology

Institutions

Invisible hand

Loyalty

Modernity

Morality

Public

Mores

National character

Natural law

Reification

Ressentiment

Rights

Sittlichkeit

Social alienation

Social norms

Spontaneous order

Stewardship

Traditions

Values

Family

Volksgeist

Worldview

Schools

Budapest School

Catholic social teaching

Distributism

Communitarianism

Confucianism

Conservatism

Social

Frankfurt School

Personalism

PhilosophersAncient

Augustine

Cicero

Confucius

Lactantius

Laozi

Mencius

Mozi

Origen

Philo

Plato

Plutarch

Polybius

Tertullian

Thucydides

Xunzi

Medieval

Alpharabius

Aquinas

Avempace

Bruni

Dante

Gelasius

Ibn Khaldun

Maimonides

Muhammad

Photios

Plethon

Ibn Tufayl

Early modern

Calvin

Erasmus

Guicciardini

Locke

Luther

Milton

Montaigne

Müntzer

18th and 19thcenturies

Arnold

Bentham

Bonald

Burke

Carlyle

Comte

Condorcet

Emerson

Engels

Fichte

Fourier

Franklin

Hegel

Helvétius

Herder

Hume

Jefferson

Kant

Kierkegaard

Le Bon

Le Play

Marx

Mill

Nietzsche

Owen

Renan

Rousseau

Royce

Ruskin

Smith

Spencer

de Staël

Stirner

Taine

Thoreau

Tocqueville

Vico

Vivekananda

Voltaire

20th and 21stcenturies

Adorno

Agamben

Arendt

Aron

Badiou

Baudrillard

Bauman

Benoist

Berlin

Butler

Camus

de Beauvoir

Debord

Deleuze

Dewey

Du Bois

Durkheim

Eco

Evola

Foucault

Fromm

Gandhi

Gehlen

Gentile

Gramsci

Guénon

Habermas

Han

Heidegger

Hoppe

Irigaray

Kirk

Kołakowski

Kropotkin

Land

Lasch

MacIntyre

Marcuse

Maritain

Negri

Niebuhr

Nussbaum

Oakeshott

Ortega

Pareto

Polanyi

Radhakrishnan

Röpke

Santayana

Scruton

Shariati

Simmel

Skinner

Sombart

Sowell

Spengler

Taylor

Voegelin

Walzer

Weber

Weil

Zinn

Žižek

Works

De Officiis (44 BC)

Oration on the Dignity of Man (1486)

A Vindication of Natural Society (1756)

Democracy in America (1835–1840)

Civilization and Its Discontents (1930)

The Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction (1935)

The Second Sex (1949)

One-Dimensional Man (1964)

The Society of the Spectacle (1967)

The History of Sexuality (1976)

The Culture of Narcissism (1979)

A Conflict of Visions (1987)

The Closing of the American Mind (1987)

Gender Trouble (1990)

The Malaise of Modernity (1991)

Intellectuals and Society (2010)

See also

Agnotology

Axiology

Critical theory

Cultural criticism

Cultural pessimism

Ethics

Historism

Historicism

Humanities

Philosophy of culture

Philosophy of education

Philosophy of history

Political philosophy

Social criticism

Social science

Social theory

Sociology

Category

Authority control databases National

Spain

France

BnF data

Germany

Israel

United States

Latvia

Japan

Czech Republic

Other

Encyclopedia of Modern Ukraine

NARA

Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Ethics&oldid=1213131758"

Categories: EthicsMain topic articlesHidden categories: Good articlesArticles with short descriptionShort description is different from WikidataUse mdy dates from November 2014Articles containing Ancient Greek (to 1453)-language textArticles containing Latin-language textArticles containing French-language textPages using multiple image with auto scaled imagesPages using Sister project links with hidden wikidataArticles containing German-language textArticles with BNE identifiersArticles with BNF identifiersArticles with BNFdata identifiersArticles with GND identifiersArticles with J9U identifiersArticles with LCCN identifiersArticles with LNB identifiersArticles with NDL identifiersArticles with NKC identifiersArticles with EMU identifiersArticles with NARA identifiers

This page was last edited on 11 March 2024, at 07:56 (UTC).

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License 4.0;

additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.

Privacy policy

About Wikipedia

Disclaimers

Contact Wikipedia

Code of Conduct

Developers

Statistics

Cookie statement

Mobile view

Toggle limited content width

2.3 Ethical Concerns - Introduction to Sociology 3e | OpenStax

Ethical Concerns - Introduction to Sociology 3e | OpenStaxSkip to ContentGo to accessibility pageKeyboard shortcuts menuIntroduction to Sociology 3e2.3 Ethical ConcernsIntroduction to Sociology 3e2.3 Ethical ConcernsSearchSearchCloseSearchContentsContentsHighlightsPrintTable of contentsPreface1

An Introduction to SociologyIntroduction1.1 What Is Sociology?1.2 The History of Sociology1.3 Theoretical Perspectives in Sociology1.4 Why Study Sociology?Key TermsSection SummarySection QuizShort AnswerFurther ResearchReferences2

Sociological ResearchIntroduction2.1 Approaches to Sociological Research2.2 Research Methods2.3 Ethical ConcernsKey TermsSection SummarySection QuizShort AnswerFurther ResearchReferences3

CultureIntroduction3.1 What Is Culture?3.2 Elements of Culture3.3 High, Low, Pop, Sub, Counter-culture and Cultural Change3.4 Theoretical Perspectives on CultureKey TermsSection SummarySection QuizShort AnswerFurther ResearchReferences4

Society and Social InteractionIntroduction4.1 Types of Societies4.2 Theoretical Perspectives on Society4.3 Social Constructions of RealityKey TermsSection SummarySection QuizShort AnswerFurther ResearchReferences5

SocializationIntroduction5.1 Theories of Self-Development5.2 Why Socialization Matters5.3 Agents of Socialization5.4 Socialization Across the Life CourseKey TermsSection SummarySection QuizShort AnswerFurther ResearchReferences6

Groups and OrganizationIntroduction6.1 Types of Groups6.2 Group Size and Structure6.3 Formal OrganizationsKey TermsSection SummarySection QuizShort AnswerFurther ResearchReferences7

Deviance, Crime, and Social ControlIntroduction7.1 Deviance and Control7.2 Theoretical Perspectives on Deviance and Crime7.3 Crime and the LawKey TermsSection SummarySection QuizShort AnswerFurther ResearchReferences8

Media and TechnologyIntroduction8.1 Technology Today8.2 Media and Technology in Society8.3 Global Implications of Media and Technology8.4 Theoretical Perspectives on Media and TechnologyKey TermsSection SummarySection QuizShort AnswerFurther ResearchReferences9

Social Stratification in the United StatesIntroduction9.1 What Is Social Stratification?9.2 Social Stratification and Mobility in the United States9.3 Global Stratification and Inequality9.4 Theoretical Perspectives on Social StratificationKey TermsSection SummarySection QuizShort AnswerFurther ResearchReferences10

Global InequalityIntroduction10.1 Global Stratification and Classification10.2 Global Wealth and Poverty10.3 Theoretical Perspectives on Global StratificationKey TermsSection SummarySection QuizShort AnswerFurther ResearchReferences11

Race and EthnicityIntroduction11.1 Racial, Ethnic, and Minority Groups11.2 Theoretical Perspectives on Race and Ethnicity11.3 Prejudice, Discrimination, and Racism11.4 Intergroup Relationships11.5 Race and Ethnicity in the United StatesKey TermsSection SummarySection QuizShort AnswerFurther ResearchReferences12

Gender, Sex, and SexualityIntroduction12.1 Sex, Gender, Identity, and Expression12.2 Gender and Gender Inequality12.3 SexualityKey TermsSection SummarySection QuizShort AnswerFurther ResearchReferences13

Aging and the ElderlyIntroduction13.1 Who Are the Elderly? Aging in Society13.2 The Process of Aging13.3 Challenges Facing the Elderly13.4 Theoretical Perspectives on AgingKey TermsSection SummarySection QuizShort AnswerFurther ResearchReferences14

Relationships, Marriage, and FamilyIntroduction14.1 What Is Marriage? What Is a Family?14.2 Variations in Family Life14.3 Challenges Families FaceKey TermsSection SummarySection QuizShort AnswerFurther ResearchReferences15

ReligionIntroduction15.1 The Sociological Approach to Religion15.2 World Religions15.3 Religion in the United StatesKey TermsSection SummarySection QuizShort AnswerFurther ResearchReferences16

EducationIntroduction16.1 Education around the World16.2 Theoretical Perspectives on Education16.3 Issues in EducationKey TermsSection SummarySection QuizShort AnswerFurther ResearchReferences17

Government and PoliticsIntroduction17.1 Power and Authority17.2 Forms of Government17.3 Politics in the United States17.4 Theoretical Perspectives on Government and PowerKey TermsSection SummarySection QuizShort AnswerFurther ResearchReferences18

Work and the EconomyIntroduction to Work and the Economy18.1 Economic Systems18.2 Globalization and the Economy18.3 Work in the United StatesKey TermsSection SummarySection QuizShort AnswerFurther ResearchReferences19

Health and MedicineIntroduction19.1 The Social Construction of Health19.2 Global Health19.3 Health in the United States19.4 Comparative Health and Medicine19.5 Theoretical Perspectives on Health and MedicineKey TermsSection SummarySection QuizShort AnswerFurther ResearchReferences20

Population, Urbanization, and the EnvironmentIntroduction20.1 Demography and Population20.2 Urbanization20.3 The Environment and SocietyKey TermsSection SummarySection QuizShort AnswerFurther ResearchReferences21

Social Movements and Social ChangeIntroduction to Social Movements and Social Change21.1 Collective Behavior21.2 Social Movements21.3 Social ChangeKey TermsSection SummarySection QuizShort AnswerReferencesAnswer KeyChapter 1Chapter 2Chapter 3Chapter 4Chapter 5Chapter 6Chapter 7Chapter 8Chapter 9Chapter 10Chapter 11Chapter 12Chapter 13Chapter 14Chapter 15Chapter 16Chapter 17Chapter 18Chapter 19Chapter 20Chapter 21IndexLearning ObjectivesBy the end of this section, you should be able to:

Understand why ethical standards exist

Investigate unethical studies

Demonstrate awareness of the American Sociological Association’s Code of Ethics

Sociologists conduct studies to shed light on human behaviors. Knowledge is a powerful tool that can be used to achieve positive change. As a result, conducting a sociological study comes with a tremendous amount of responsibility. Like all researchers, sociologists must consider their ethical obligation to avoid harming human subjects or groups while conducting research.

Pioneer German sociologist Max Weber (1864–1920) identified another crucial ethical concern. Weber understood that personal values could distort the framework for disclosing study results. While he accepted that some aspects of research design might be influenced by personal values, he declared it was entirely inappropriate to allow personal values to shape the interpretation of the responses. Sociologists, he stated, must establish value neutrality, a practice of remaining impartial, without bias or judgment, during the course of a study and in publishing results (Weber, 1949). Sociologists are obligated to disclose research findings without omitting or distorting significant data.

Is value neutrality possible? Many sociologists believe it is impossible to retain complete objectivity. They caution readers, rather, to understand that sociological studies may contain a certain amount of value bias. This does not discredit the results, but allows readers to view them as one form of truth—one fact-based perspective. Some sociologists attempt to remain uncritical and as objective as possible when studying social institutions. They strive to overcome personal biases, particularly subconscious biases, when collecting and analyzing data. They avoid skewing data in order to match a predetermined outcome that aligns with a particular agenda, such as a political or moral point of view. Investigators are ethically obligated to report results, even when they contradict personal views, predicted outcomes, or widely accepted beliefs.

The American Sociological Association, or ASA, is the major professional organization of sociologists in North America. The ASA is a great resource for students of sociology as well. The ASA maintains a code of ethics—formal guidelines for conducting sociological research—consisting of principles and ethical standards to be used in the discipline. These formal guidelines were established by practitioners in 1905 at John Hopkins University, and revised in 1997. When working with human subjects, these codes of ethics require researchers to do the following:

Maintain objectivity and integrity in research

Respect subjects’ rights to privacy and dignity

Protect subject from personal harm

Preserve confidentiality

Seek informed consent

Acknowledge collaboration and assistance

Disclose sources of financial support

Unfortunately, when these codes of ethics are ignored, it creates an unethical environment for humans being involved in a sociological study. Throughout history, there have been numerous unethical studies, some of which are summarized below.

Figure

2.11

Participants in the Tuskegee study were denied important information about their diagnosis, leading to significant health issues. (Credit: Centers for Disease Control)

The Tuskegee Experiment: This study was conducted 1932 in Macon County, Alabama, and included 600 African American men, including 399 diagnosed with syphilis. The participants were told they were diagnosed with a disease of “bad blood.” Penicillin was distributed in the 1940s as the cure for the disease, but unfortunately, the African American men were not given the treatment because the objective of the study was to see “how untreated syphilis would affect the African American male” (Caplan, 2007)

Henrietta Lacks: Ironically, this study was conducted at the hospital associated with Johns Hopkins University, where the ASA codes of ethics originated. In 1951, Henrietta Lacks was receiving treatment for cervical cancer at John Hopkins Hospital, and doctors discovered that she had “immortal” cells, which could reproduce rapidly and indefinitely, making them extremely valuable for medical research. Without her consent, doctors collected and shared her cells to produce extensive cell lines. Lacks’ cells were widely used for experiments and treatments, including the polio vaccine, and were put into mass production. Today, these cells are known worldwide as HeLa cells (Shah, 2010).

Milgram Experiment: In 1961, psychologist Stanley Milgram conducted an experiment at Yale University. Its purpose was to measure the willingness of study subjects to obey an authority figure who instructed them to perform acts that conflicted with their personal conscience. People in the role of teacher believed they were administering electric shocks to students who gave incorrect answers to word-pair questions. No matter how concerned they were about administering the progressively more intense shocks, the teachers were told to keep going. The ethical concerns involve the extreme emotional distress faced by the teachers, who believed they were hurting other people. (Vogel 2014).

Philip Zimbardo and the Stanford prison experiment: In 1971, psychologist Phillip Zimbardo conducted a study involving students from Stanford University. The students were put in the roles of prisoners and guards, and were required to play their assigned role accordingly. The experiment was intended to last two weeks, but it only lasted six days due to the negative outcome and treatment of the “prisoners.” Beyond the ethical concerns, the study’s validity has been questioned after participants revealed they had been coached to behave in specific ways.

Laud Humphreys: In the 1960s, Laud Humphreys conducted an experiment at a restroom in a park known for same-sex sexual encounters. His objective was to understand the diversity of backgrounds and motivations of people seeking same-sex relationships. His ethics were questioned because he misrepresented his identity and intent while observing and questioning the men he interviewed (Nardi, 1995).

PreviousNextOrder a print copyAs an Amazon Associate we earn from qualifying purchases.Citation/Attribution

This book may not be used in the training of large language models or otherwise be ingested into large language models or generative AI offerings without OpenStax's permission.

Want to cite, share, or modify this book? This book uses the

Creative Commons Attribution License

and you must attribute OpenStax.

Attribution information

If you are redistributing all or part of this book in a print format,

then you must include on every physical page the following attribution:

Access for free at https://openstax.org/books/introduction-sociology-3e/pages/1-introduction

If you are redistributing all or part of this book in a digital format,

then you must include on every digital page view the following attribution:

Access for free at https://openstax.org/books/introduction-sociology-3e/pages/1-introduction

Citation information

Use the information below to generate a citation. We recommend using a

citation tool such as

this one.

Authors: Tonja R. Conerly, Kathleen Holmes, Asha Lal Tamang

Publisher/website: OpenStax

Book title: Introduction to Sociology 3e

Publication date: Jun 3, 2021

Location: Houston, Texas

Book URL: https://openstax.org/books/introduction-sociology-3e/pages/1-introduction

Section URL: https://openstax.org/books/introduction-sociology-3e/pages/2-3-ethical-concerns

© Jan 18, 2024 OpenStax. Textbook content produced by OpenStax is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution License . The OpenStax name, OpenStax logo, OpenStax book covers, OpenStax CNX name, and OpenStax CNX logo

are not subject to the Creative Commons license and may not be reproduced without the prior and express written

consent of Rice University.

Our mission is to improve educational access and learning for everyone.

OpenStax is part of Rice University, which is a 501(c)(3) nonprofit.

Give today and help us reach more students.

HelpContact UsSupport CenterFAQOpenStaxPressNewsletterCareersPoliciesAccessibility StatementTerms of UseLicensingPrivacy Policy

© 1999-2024, Rice University. Except where otherwise noted, textbooks on this site

are licensed under a

Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.

Advanced Placement® and AP® are trademarks registered and/or owned by the College Board,

which is not affiliated with, and does not endorse, this site.

Ethics

Ethics

Global

Regions

WHO Regional websites

Africa

Americas

South-East Asia

Europe

Eastern Mediterranean

Western Pacific

When autocomplete results are available use up and down arrows to review and enter to select.

Select language

Select language

English

العربية

Home

Health Topics

All topicsABCDEFGHIJKLMNOPQRSTUVWXYZ

Resources

Fact sheets

Facts in pictures

Multimedia

Publications

Questions and answers

Tools and toolkits

Popular

COVID-19

Dengue

Herpes

Hypertension

Mental disorders

Top 10 causes of death

Countries

All countriesABCDEFGHIJKLMNOPQRSTUVWXYZ

Regions

Africa

Americas

Europe

Eastern Mediterranean

South-East Asia

Western Pacific

WHO in countries

Cooperation strategies

Data by country

Newsroom

All news

News releases

Statements

Campaigns

Events

Feature stories

Speeches

Commentaries

Photo library

Headlines

Emergencies

Focus on

Afghanistan

Cholera 

Greater Horn of Africa

Israel and occupied Palestinian territory

Sudan

Ukraine

Latest

Disease Outbreak News

Situation reports

Weekly Epidemiological Record

WHO in emergencies

Surveillance

Operations

Research

Funding

Partners

Health emergency appeal

International Health Regulations

Independent Oversight and Advisory Committee

Data

Data at WHO

Classifications

Data collections

Global Health Estimates

Mortality Database

Sustainable Development Goals

Dashboards

COVID-19

Health Inequality Monitor

Triple Billion

Highlights

Data collection tools

Global Health Observatory

Insights and visualizations

SCORE

Reports

COVID excess deaths

World Health Statistics

About WHO

About WHO

Partnerships

Committees and advisory groups

Collaborating centres

Technical teams

Organizational structure

Who we are

Our work

Activities

Initiatives

Global Programme of Work

WHO Academy

Funding

Investment case

WHO Foundation

Accountability

Audit

Financial statements

Programme budget

Results Report

Governance

Governing bodies

World Health Assembly

Executive Board

Member States Portal

Home/

Health topics/

Ethics and health

WHO

©

Credits

Global health ethics

Overview

Ethical questions related to health, health care, and public health cover topics as diverse as moral issues around reproduction, state obligations in the provision of health care services, and appropriate measures to control infectious disease. Scholars and health care professionals have debated ethical questions related to health and health care since the earliest days of medicine. Recent formal efforts to articulate international standards of ethics applicable to health and health care can

be traced to the Nuremberg trials of 1947, during which the horrors of Nazi medical experiments came to light.The principles that emerged from those trials, known as the Nuremberg Code, are broadly applicable to many types of health-related research involving

human participants, including clinical trials. The growing breadth and complexity of contemporary health challenges have produced a range of difficult questions that cannot always be adequately addressed by relying exclusively on existing policies,

guidelines or codes of conduct. Debates over access to new and expensive pharmaceuticals and medical technologies, as well as increasing awareness of the gross health disparities that exist both within and between countries, have called attention to the

need for an ethics of health policy and practice.

Research

Research ethics govern the standards of conduct for scientific researchers. It is important to adhere to ethical principles in order to protect the dignity, rights and welfare of research participants.The WHO Manual (Section XV.2) defines research with human subjects as 'any social science, biomedical, behavioural, or epidemiological activity that entails systematic collection or analysis of data with the intent to generate new knowledge, in which human beings:are exposed to manipulation, intervention, observation, or other interaction with investigators either directly or through alteration of their environment; or

become individually identifiable through investigator's collection, preparation, or use of biological material or medical or other records.

Infectious diseases

Immunization raises a host of challenging ethical questions that researchers, governments, funders, pharmaceutical companies, and communities must confront.TB: Ethical issues include questions about the equitable distribution of resources, protection of vulnerable groups, respect for patient choice of treatment options and solidarity between communities during outbreaks.Zika has raised many specific ethical issues, in particular regarding pregnancy. At the same time, it has highlighted ethical issues that arise in vector-borne diseases more generally.The HIV epidemic has raised many ethical challenges for public health officials, researchers and clinicians, reaching from macro-level policy to micro-level clinical decisions.

Questions and answers  Questions and answers about ethicsEthics and COVID-19: resource allocation and priority settingDatabases and tools  Human Genome Editing (HGE) RegistryInitiatives and groups  Expert Group on Ethics and Governance of Artificial Intelligence for Health Technical work Health Ethics & GovernanceEthics and COVID-19 

News

All →

18 January 2024

News release

WHO releases AI ethics and governance guidance for large multi-modal models

11 December 2023

Departmental news

New Technical Advisory Group on Embedding Ethics in Health and Climate Change Policy (TAG-Ethics & Climate Health)

25 September 2023

Departmental news

Launch of WHO tool for benchmarking ethics oversight of health-related research involving human participants

10 February 2023

Departmental news

WHO kicks off deliberations on ethical framework and tools for social listening and infodemic management

Publications

All →

19 June 2017

WHO guidelines on ethical issues in public health surveillance

This document outlines 17 ethical guidelines that can assist everyone involved in public health surveillance, including officials in government agencies,...

Download

Read More

18 January 2024

Ethics and governance of artificial intelligence for health: Guidance on large multi-modal models

Artificial Intelligence (AI) refers to the capability of algorithms integrated into systems

and tools to learn from data so that they can perform automated...

Download

Read More

1 October 2023

Ethics and adaptive platform trial design in public health emergencies: meeting report,18-19 July 2022,...

Platform trials using adaptive methods have played a key role in the research response to COVID-19. They raise important ethical issues, however,...

Download

Read More

25 September 2023

WHO tool for benchmarking ethics oversight of health-related research involving human participants: user...

Jointly developed by WHO’s Regulatory System Strengthening, Regulation and Safety Unit and the Health Ethics & Governance Unit, it is intended...

Download

Read More

25 September 2023

WHO tool for benchmarking ethics oversight of health-related research involving human participants 

Jointly developed by WHO’s Regulatory System Strengthening, Regulation and Safety Unit and the Health Ethics & Governance Unit, it is intended...

Download

Read More

Our work

All →

Ensuring ethical standards and procedures for research with human beings

Developing normative guidance to address ethical challenges in global health

Supporting countries to manage ethical issues during outbreaks and emergencies

Engaging the global community in health ethics

Building ethics capacity

Framing the ethics of public health surveillance

Videos

All →

27 October 2022

Has the decolonizing global health agenda been colonized?

6 December 2021

WHO Pandemic Ethics & Policy Summit: Dr Fifa A Rahman, Civil Society Representative

6 December 2021

WHO Pandemic Ethics & Policy Summit: Prof David Archer, Chairperson of Nuffield Council on Bioethics

6 December 2021

WHO Pandemic Ethics & Policy Summit - Charu Kauschic Chair of the Glopid-R Network

Partners

UN-Interagency CommitteeCountry Coordinating Mechanism - The Global Fund to Fight AIDS, Tuberculosis and Malaria

Quiz

The ethics of public health surveillance

Related health topics

Communicable diseases

HIV

Other

Human genome editing

Health interventions

Vaccines and immunization

Regions

Africa

Americas

Eastern Mediterranean

Europe

South-East Asia

Western Pacific

Policies

Cyber security

Ethics

Permissions and licensing

Preventing sexual exploitation

Terms of use

About us

Careers

Library

Procurement

Publications

Frequently asked questions

Contact us

Report misconduct

Privacy policy

©

2024

WHO